In the following, it will be conceptualized how from the universal right to health and to healthcare follows a sustainable right to health and to healthcare. Before doing so, I will briefly summarise what I refer to as the economic, or the traditional, concept of sustainability, which originated in economic sciences and has been discussed in business ethics. In 1987, the UN's World Commission on Environment and Development (WCED) adopted the so-called Brundtland Report Our Common Future, where it set forth in paragraph 1 of the conclusion of chapter 2:
Sustainable development is development that meets the needs of the present without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their own needs. It contains within it two key concepts: the concept of ‘needs’, in particular the essential needs of the world's poor, to which overriding priority should be given; and the idea of limitations imposed by the state of technology and social organization on the environment's ability to meet present and future needs. (WCED, 1987, chapter 2)
Thereafter, in the 1990s, economist John Elkington formed the concept of a “triple bottom line” sustainability approach aiming at measurability of the sustainability of businesses. Since then, the concept has quickly been widely adopted “in management, consulting, investing, and NGO circles” (Norman and MacDonald, 2004, p. 243), as well as broadly discussed from the perspective of business ethics. Whilst a literature review of the discussion on the ethical aspects of the triple bottom line approach is beyond the scope of this paper, it could start by analysing the vast amount of articles including the term “triple bottom line” that have been published in the Journal of Business Ethics.
Like the WCED, Elkington defines sustainability with reference to future generations: “Sustainability is the principle of ensuring that our actions today do not limit the range of economic, social, and environmental options open to future generations” (Elkington, 1999, p. 20). This has been the point of origination of my interest in his approach for a discussion of the value of health and healthcare from an ethical perspective. For if there is a universal right to health and healthcare, it follows that not only at present but also in the future, entitlements to this right uphold, i.e., as has been stated above, that to grant the right to health to everyone, a healthy environment, healthy social conditions, and the provision of healthcare do not only have to be created but also sustained. Therefore, the right to health and to healthcare if universal, needs to be sustainable and sustained for future generations. In cases where potential health services or health technologies would or could negatively affect the health of future generations, the sustainable right to health and to healthcare is violated. This is one reason why a potential health technology that generates inheritable changes in the patient is regarded as ethically unacceptable, and why the aspect of effect on future generations is an important ethical criterion in the debate on germline genome editing, as germline genome editing might be unsustainable. In search of an approach to integrate the aspect of future generations in a broader conception of the value of healthcare, the concept of sustainability, therefore, presented itself as highly suitable.
However, Elkington's triple bottom line approach cannot be copied, as it stands, for a concept of sustainable health and healthcare, especially since his aim is to use the approach for business accounting. He, thus, takes an economic perspective that is not suitable for an ethical view on the right to health(care). By including the “social bottom line”, the “economic bottom line”, and the “environmental bottom line” into his approach (pp. 73f.), he argues that all of these can be taken together to “assess a company's […] performance”, in the way that “accountants pull together, record and analyze a wide range of numerical data” (p. 74). The hierarchy of the three bottom lines be defined by their interdependencies: “Society depends on the economy – and the economy depends on the global ecosystem, whose health represents the ultimate bottom line” (p. 73). Because Elkington especially points to values that influenced his approach (in a chapter of his book from 1999 named accordingly, pp. 123–158), “such as concern for future generations” (p. 124), it is justified to see his intention in the fact that the social and the environmental bottom line are supposed to integrate ethical aspects into business accounting. Therefore, it would have been necessary that he clarified why he, on the one hand, separates the economic bottom line from the other two, ethically oriented, bottom lines but, on the other hand, frames the entire approach as one of accounting, hence, one of economics, and not one of ethics. As MacDonald and Norman (2007) have argued in response to Pava (2007) Pava (2007) responded to the paper by Norman and MacDonald (2004) quoted above):
the accounting paradigm is inappropriate as a comprehensive methodology for the ethical evaluation of a firm and its operations. Crucially qualitative distinctions – especially deontic distinctions between different kinds of obligations and responsibilities – would be bulldozed over by an entirely quantitative evaluation scheme. (MacDonald and Norman, 2007, p. 112; emphasis in original)
Aligning with John Elkington (1999) but considering the criticism of his approach and in recourse to the WCED's definition of sustainable development, I understand the traditional concept of sustainability as including social aspects (as a concern for present as well as future generations), economic aspects (as the “[s]ociety depends on the economy”; Elkington, 1999, p. 73), and environmental aspects (as “the economy depends on the global ecosystem”; ibid.; but especially as society depends on the health of the environment).
3.2 The concept of a sustainable right to health
Daniel D. Reidpath and colleagues, in their article “Is the right to health compatible with sustainability?” (Journal of Global Health, 2015) argue that the universal right to health as understood by the ICESCR (1966) conflicts with sustainability (Reidpath et al., 2015, p. 1). Measuring sustainability by reference to a country's per capita ecological footprint, and assessing realisation of the right to the highest attainable standard of health (HASH) by taking life expectancy as a HASH point, an analysis of 147 countries, conducted in 2008, revealed that countries with the highest HASH point were significantly less sustainable than countries with lower HASH points (p. 2). The authors, therefore, claim to replace the right to the highest attainable standard of health by “a fundamental human right to the highest sustainable standard of health” (p. 3; emphasis in original).
As has been shown in the previous section, I do not agree with Reidpath and colleagues’ negative answer to the question “Is the right to health compatible with sustainability?”. I understand the universal right to health as comprising a sustainable right to health, as the latter follows from the former. I, therefore, do agree with the request of Reidpath and colleagues to alleviate the problem that “at a population level, the highest attainable standard of health is a standard that is achieved (or progressively realised) through unsustainable levels of consumption” (Reidpath et al., 2015, p. 1). In order to mitigate this problem, I suggest that the universal right to health can, firstly, only be realised at an international level, which transcends the “population level”, and, secondly, must be understood as a sustainable right to health that includes the right to health of future generations.
However, I do not think that such a concept of a sustainable right to health is limited to the mitigation of “unsustainable levels of consumption”, but that it is also suitable to prevent problems resulting from the implementation of certain health technologies or specific practices in healthcare, inasmuch as these technologies or practices might result in a successful treatment of one patient at the cost of the health or even the life of another human being. Here again, I may refer to the example of assisted reproductive medicine.
As in germline genome editing, the embryo that is edited might be successfully treated but might, nevertheless, bequeath unintended effects of the treatment to its descendants and, accordingly, pass on a negative effect to the health of future generations (e.g., cf. Petre, 2017; Schöne-Seifert, 2017), so too, in another form of reproductive medicine, negative effects on the health of human beings are negative side effects. Selective embryo transfer following in vitro fertilization or preimplantation genetic diagnosis is an apt example. These health technologies are applied to cure the infertility of couples, hence, in respect for the agent-relative reproductive rights (as part of the universal right to health) of patients who are unable to have (healthy) children naturally. Respect for these agent-relative rights may disregard the agent-neutral right to health (and life) of the embryos that are discarded or selected against in the process of the treatment, at least if these embryos have intrinsic value that justifies their agent-neutral right to health (including a right to life). In both examples, granting of the right to health disregards the sustainable right to health of future generations.
If it is considered that, also in the process of germline genome editing, embryo selection cannot be avoided (e.g., cf. Ranisch, 2020, p. 64; Wells, 2019, p. 347), those embryos that are successfully edited are those whose right to health is respected, but it is respected at the cost of the discarding of other embryos in the process of the application of the technology. Hence, respect for the right to health of successfully edited embryos in the case of genome editing comes at the cost of disregard for the right to health (and life) of other embryos that have been created at around the same time as the successfully edited embryos, and are, therefore, (from the point of view of the successfully edited embryos) not members of future generations but of the same generation. Similarly, one can argue that the right to health of members of the same generation is affected by healthcare for other members of that same generation in cases of “[t]he prevention, treatment and control of epidemic, endemic, occupational and other diseases” (ICESCR, 1966, Art. 12, para. 2, c), such as immunization, but also as triage and allocation of scarce resources (e.g., cf. ÖGARI, 2020). The latter has been the focus of medical ethics during the SARS-CoV-2/COVID-19 pandemic that, at the time of writing this article, remains an unsolved global problem.
Summing up these examples, it can be stated that viewing the right to health from the perspective of sustainability does allow for an approach to realise the agent-neutral right to health, including the right to health of future generations as well as of all members of the global community of present generations. Thus, one aspect of the concept of a sustainable right to health resembles the component “societal aspects” of the traditional concept of sustainability. Furthermore, it is especially important to sustain healthy social conditions to fulfil the right to health inasmuch as it transcends the right to healthcare (cf. CESCR, 2000, para. 4).
As has also been shown in the examples, the agent-relative right to health of specific individuals in specific situations is another important aspect of a sustainable right to health. To only reiterate one example, the reproductive health is important when deciding whether to undertake preimplantation genetic diagnosis. Equally important in this case may be the right to health and life of specific embryos that might be discarded in the process of the infertility treatment. Depending on the point of view, either of those rights can be described as agent-relative, as either of those rights indeed is agent-relative as well as agent-neutral. However, when the perspective of the (potential) parents is taken, their reproductive rights are agent-relative as they result from their specific intrinsic value as human beings.
Especially when conceptualizing the sustainable right to healthcare (see next section), the patient in a specific patient-physician relationship can be viewed as the agent whose agent-relative right to healthcare needs to be primarily considered (cf. DeCamp, 2019), although it may be possible to discuss with the patient how treatment for her/him influences the availability of treatment for other patients through economic aspects, i.e. costs of her/his individual treatment (cf. DeCamp 2019, pp. 238f.; Pearson, 2000). A third aspect of a sustainable right to health, therefore, is the economic aspect. Contrary to Elkington's approach on sustainability, from an ethical perspective, the economic aspect can only be viewed as instrumental to the fulfilment of the agent-relative and agent-neutral sustainable right to health. Nevertheless, this aspect resembles the economic aspect of the traditional concept of sustainability.
Finally, a fourth aspect is similar to the traditional concept of sustainability; this is the inclusion of environmental aspects into a sustainable right to health, as it is especially important to sustain not only healthy social but also healthy environmental conditions in order to fulfil the right to health inasmuch as it transcends the right to healthcare (cf. CESCR, 2000, para. 4).
It can, thus, be concluded that the concept of a sustainable right to health comprises the agent-relative right to health (health of individual with intrinsic value, in a specific situation), the agent-neutral right to health (health of each individual within the global society, at present and in future; healthy social conditions to sustain the right to health), economic aspects (inasmuch as they are necessary to fulfil agent-relative and agent-neutral rights to health), environmental aspects (healthy environmental conditions to sustain the right to health).
3.3 The concept of a sustainable right to healthcare
As there is a universal and sustainable right to health, there is also a universal and sustainable right to healthcare for, as stated in ICESCR (1966) and CESCR (2000), the right to health encompasses the right to healthcare. This has been outlined above. Furthermore, in the previous section, the four components of a sustainable right to health have been described. Those already comprise the three components of the sustainable right to healthcare.
The sustainable right to healthcare, thus, encompasses the agent-relative right to healthcare (of an individual patient, such as in a specific patient-physician relationship; cf. DeCamp, 2019, pp. 235ff.), the agent-neutral right to healthcare (of each present and future member of society), economic aspects (especially of the health economy; no economic interests that are beyond moral interests, i.e. none that exceed guaranteeing a sustainable right to healthcare).
Because the sustainable right to healthcare depicts the component of the sustainable right to health that refers to healthcare, it does not include the other components and conditions for health. As such, its scope is narrower. This is the reason why environmental aspects are not included as a fourth component.