NCBI Bookshelf. A service of the National Library of Medicine, National Institutes of Health.
National Research Council (US) Steering Committee on Valuing Health Risks, Costs, and Benefits for Environmental Decisions; Hammond PB, Coppock R, editors. Valuing Health Risks, Costs, and Benefits for Environmental Decision Making: Report of a Conference. Washington (DC): National Academies Press (US); 1990.
Valuing Health Risks, Costs, and Benefits for Environmental Decision Making: Report of a Conference.
Show detailsMark J. Machina
Fifteen years ago, the theory of choice under uncertainty could be considered one of the "success stories" of economic analysis: it rested on solid axiomatic foundations;1 it had seen important breakthroughs in the analytics of risk and risk aversion and their applications to economic issues;2 and it stood ready to provide the theoretical underpinnings for the newly emerging "information revolution" in economics.3 Today, choice under uncertainty is a field in flux: the standard theory and, implicitly, its public policy implications are being challenged on several grounds from both within and outside the field of economics. The nature of these challenges, and of economists' responses to them, is the topic of this paper.
The following section provides a brief but self-contained description of the economist's canonical model of individual choice under uncertainty, the expected utility model of preferences over lotteries. I shall describe this model from two different perspectives. The first perspective is the most familiar and has traditionally been the most useful for addressing standard economic questions. However, the second, more modem perspective will be the most useful for illustrating some of the problems that have beset this model, as well as some of the proposed responses.
Each of the following sections is devoted to one of these problems. All are important; some are more completely "solved" than others. In each case, I begin with a specific example or description of the phenomenon in question. I then review the empirical evidence regarding the uniformity and extent of the phenomenon. Finally, I shall report on how these findings have changed, or are likely to change, or should change, the way economists view and model private and public decisions under uncertainty. On this last topic, the disclaimer that "my opinions are my own" has more than the usual significance.
The Expected Utility Model
The Classical Perspective: Cardinal Utility And Attitudes Toward Risk
In light of current trends toward generalizing this model, it is useful to note that the expected utility hypothesis was itself first proposed as an alternative to an earlier, more restrictive theory of risk-bearing. During the development of modern probability theory in the 17th century, such mathematicians as Blaise Pascal and Pierre de Fermat assumed that the attractiveness of a gamble offering the payoffs (x1 ..., xn) with probabilities (p1, ..., pn) was given by its expected value x (i.e., the weighted average of the payoffs where each payoff is multiplied by its associated probability, so that ). The fact that individuals consider more than just expected value, however, was dramatically illustrated by an example posed by Nicholas Bernoulli in 1728 and now known as the St. Petersburg Paradox:
Suppose someone offers to toss a fair coin repeatedly until it comes up heads, and to pay you $1 if this happens on the first toss, $2 if it takes two tosses to land a head, $4 if it takes three tosses, $8 if it takes four tosses, and so on. What is the largest sure payment you would be willing to forgo in order to undertake a single play of this game?
Because this gamble offers a 1/2 chance of winning $1, a 1/4 chance of winning $2, and so forth, its expected value is ; thus, it should be preferred to any finite sure gain. However, it is clear that few individuals would forgo more than a moderate amount for a one-shot play. Although the unlimited financial backing needed to actually make this offer is somewhat unrealistic, it is not essential for making the point: agreeing to limit the game to at most a million tosses will still lead to a striking discrepancy between a typical individual's valuation of the modified gamble and its expected value of $500,000.
The resolution of this paradox was proposed independently by Gabriel Cramer and Nicholas's cousin Daniel Bernoulli.4 Arguing that a gain of $2,000 was not necessarily "worth" twice as much as a gain of $1,000, they hypothesized that individuals possess what is now termed a yon Neumann-Morgenstern utility of wealth function U(·). Rather than evaluating gambles on the basis of their expected value individuals will evaluate them on the basis of their expected utility This value is calculated by weighting the utility of each possible outcome by its associated probability, and it can therefore incorporate the fact that successive increments to wealth may yield successively diminishing increments to utility. Thus, if utility took the logarithmic form (which exhibits this property of diminishing increments) and the individual's wealth at the start of the game were, let us say, $50,000, the sure gain that would yield just as much utility as taking this gamble (i.e., the individual's certainty equivalent of the gamble), would be about $9, even though the gamble has an infinite expected value.5
Although it shares the name "utility," this function U(·) is quite distinct from the ordinal utility function of standard consumer theory. Although the latter can be subjected to any monotonic transformation, a von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function is cardinal in that it can only be subjected to transformations that change the origin point or the scale (or both) of the vertical axis, but do not affect the "shape" of the function. The ability to choose the origin and scale factor is often exploited to normalize the utility function—for example, to set U(0) = 0 and U(M) = 1 for some large value M.
To see how this shape determines risk attitudes, let us consider Figures la and lb. The monotonicity of the curves in each figure reflects the property of stochastic dominance preference, by which one lottery is said to stochastically dominate another if it can be obtained from it by shifting probability from lower to higher outcome levels.6 Stochastic dominance preference is thus the probabilistic extension of the attitude that "more is better."
Consider a gamble offering a 2/3 chance of a wealth level of x' and a 1/3 chance of a wealth levels of x". The amount in the figures gives the expected value of this gamble; and give its expected utility
for the utility functions Ua(·) and Ub(·). For the concave (i.e., bowed upward) utility function Ua(·), we have , which implies that this individual would prefer a sure gain of [which would yield utility ] to the gamble. Because someone with a concave utility function will in fact always rather receive the expected value of a gamble than receive the gamble itself, concave utility functions are termed risk averse. For the convex (bowed downward) utility function Ub(·), we have . Because this preference for bearing the risk rather than receiving the expected value will also extend to all gambles, Ub(·) is termed risk-loving. In their famous article, Friedman and Savage (1948) showed how a utility function that was concave at low-wealth levels and convex at high-wealth levels could explain the behavior of individuals who both incur risk by purchasing lottery tickets as well as avoid risk by purchasing insurance.7 Algebraically, Arrow (1963, 1974), Pratt (1964) and others have shown that the degree of concavity of a utility function, as measured by the curvature index —U"(x)/U'(x), can lead to predictions of how risk attitudes, and hence behavior, will vary with wealth or across individuals in a variety of situations.8
Because a knowledge of U(·) would allow the prediction of preferences (and hence behavior) in any risky situation, experimenters and applied decision analysts are frequently interested in eliciting or recovering their subjects' (or clients') von Neumann-Morgenstern utility functions. One means of doing this is the fractile method. This approach begins by adopting the normalization U(0) = 0 and U(M) = 1 for some positive amount M and fixing a "mixture probability" , . The next step involves obtaining the individual's certainty equivalent ξ1 of a gamble yielding a 1/2 chance of M and a 1/2 chance of 0, which will have the property that U(ξ1) = 1/2.9 Finding the certainty equivalent of a gamble yielding a 1/2 chance of ξ1 and a 1/2 chance of 0 yields the value ξ2 satisfying U (ξ2) = 1/4.
Finding the certainty equivalent of a gamble yielding a 1/2 chance of M and a 1/2 chance of ξ1 yields the value ξ3 satisfying U(ξ3) = 3/4.10 By repeating this procedure (i.e., 1/8, 3/8, 5/8, 7/8, 1/16, 3/16, etc.), the utility function can (in the limit) be completely assessed.
To see how the expected utility model can be applied to risk policy, let us consider a disastrous event that is expected to occur with probability p and involve a loss L (L can be measured in either dollars or lives). In many cases, there will be some scope for influencing the magnitudes of either p or L, often at the expense of the other. For example, replacing one large planned nuclear power plant with two smaller, geographically separated plants may (to a first approximation) double the possibility that a nuclear accident will occur. However, the same action may lower the magnitude of the loss (however it is measured) if an accident occurs.
The key tool used in evaluating whether such adjustments should be undertaken is the individual's (or society's) marginal rate of substitution M RSp,L, which specifies the rate at which an individual (or society) would be willing to trade off a (small) change in p against an offsetting change in L. If the potential adjustment involves better terms than this minimum acceptable rate, it will obviously be preferred; if it involves worse terms, it will not be preferred. Although the exact value of this marginal rate of substitution will depend upon the individual's (or society's) utility function U(·), the expected utility model does offer some general guidance regardless of the shape of the utility function: namely, for a given loss magnitude L, a doubling (tripling, halving, etc.) of the loss probability p should double (triple, half, etc.) the rate at which one would be willing to trade reductions in p against increases in L.11
The discussion so far has paralleled the economic literature of the 1960s and 1970s by emphasizing the flexibility of the expected utility model in comparison with the Pascal-Fermat expected value approach. The need to analyze and respond to growing empirical challenges, however, has led economists in the 1980s to concentrate on the behavioral restrictions implied by the expected utility hypothesis. These restrictions are the subject of the next section.
A Modern Perspective: Linearity In The Probabilities As A Testable Hypothesis
As a theory of individual behavior, the expected utility model shares many of the underlying assumptions of standard economic consumer theory. In each case, it is assumed that the objects of choice, either commodity bundles or lotteries, can be unambiguously and objectively descried and that situations that ultimately imply the same set of availabilities (e.g., the same budget set) will lead to the same choice. In each case, it is also assumed that the individual is able to perform the mathematical operations necessary to actually determine the set of availabilities—for example, to add up the quantities in different sized containers or to calculate the probabilities of compound or conditional events. Finally, in each case, it is assumed that preferences are transitive, so that if an individual prefers one object (either a commodity bundle or a risky prospect) to a second, and prefers this second object to a third, he or she will prefer the first object to the third. The validity of these assumptions for choice under uncertainty is examined in later sections.
The strongest and most specific implication of the expected utility hypothesis stems from the form of the expected utility maximand or preference function U(x1)p1 +... + U(xn)pn. Although this preference function generalizes the expected value form x1p1 + ... + xnpn by dropping the property of linearity in the payoff levels (i.e., the xi's), it retains the other key property of this form, namely, linearity in the probabilities.
Graphically, the property of linearity in the probabilities may be illustrated by considering the set of all lotteries or prospects over some set of fixed outcome levels x1 << x2 << x3, which can be represented by the set of all probability triples of the form P = (p1, p2, p3) where pi = prob(xi) and p1 + p2 + p3 = 1.12 Making the substitution p2= 1- p1- p3, this set of lotteries can be represented by the points in the unit triangle in the (p1, p3) plane, as in Figure 2.13 Because upward movements in the triangle increase p3 at the expense of p2 (i.e., shift probability from the outcome x2 up to x3) and leftward movements reduce p1 to the benefit of p2 (i.e., shift probability from x1 up to x2), these movements (and, more generally, all northwest movements) lead to stochastically dominating lotteries and would accordingly be preferred. For the purposes of illustrating many of the following discussions it will be useful to plot the individual's indifference curves in this diagram; that is, the curves in the diagram that connect points of equal expected utility.14 Because each such curve will consist of the set of all (p1, p3) points that solve an equation of the form for some constant k, and because the probabilities p1 and p1, p3 enter linearly (i.e., as multiplicative coefficients) into this equation, the indifference curves will consist of parallel straight lines, with more preferred indifference curves lying to the northwest. This means that, to know an expected utility maximizer's preferences over the entire triangle, it suffices to know the slope of a single indifference curve.
To see how this diagram can be used to illustrate attitudes toward risk, let us consider Figures 3a and 3b. The dashed lines in the figures are not indifference curves but rather iso-expected value lines; that is, lines connecting points with the same expected value that are hence given by the solutions to equations of the form for some constant k. Because northeast movements along these lines do not change the expected value of the prospect but do increase the probabilities of the extreme outcomes x1 and x3 at the expense of the middle outcome x2, they are simple examples of mean preserving spreads or ''pure" increases in risk.15 When the utility function U(·) is concave (i.e., risk averse), its indifference curves can be shown to be steeper than the iso-expected value lines (Figure 3a),16 and such increases in risk will lead to less preferred indifference curves. When U(·) is convex (risk loving), its indifference curves will be flatter than the iso-expected value lines (Figure 3b), and these increases in risk will lead to more preferred indifference curves. Finally, if one compares two different utility functions, the one that is more risk averse (in the above Arrow-Pratt sense) will possess the steeper indifference curves.17
Behaviorally, the property of linearity in the probabilities can be viewed as a restriction on the individual's preferences over probability mixtures of lotteries. If and P = (p1, ..., pn) are two lotteries over a common outcome set {x1, ..., xn}, the α: (1 -α) probability mixture of P* and P is the lottery . This may be thought of as that prospect that yields the same ultimate probabilities over {x1,..., xn} as the two-stage lottery that offers an α: (1- α) chance of winning P* or P, respectively. It can be shown that expected utility maximizers will exhibit the following property, known as the independence axiom :18
If the lottery P* is preferred (respectively indifferent) to the lottery P, then the mixture αP* + (1-α)P** will be preferred (respectively indifferent) to the mixture αP + (1-α)P** for all α > 0 and P**.
This property, which is in fact equivalent to linearity in the probabilities, can be interpreted as follows:
In terms of the ultimate probabilities over the outcomes {x1,..., xn}, choosing between the mixtures αP* + (1-α)P** and αP + (1-α)P** is the same as being offered a coin with a probability 1 - α of landing tails, in which case you will obtain the lottery P**, and being asked before the flip whether you would rather have P* or P in the event of a head. Now either the coin will land tails, in which case your choice won't have mattered, or else it will land heads, in which case your are "in effect" back to a choice between P* or P, and it is only "rational" to make the same choice as you would before.
Although this is a prescriptive argument, it has played a key role in economists' adoption of expected utility as a descriptive theory of choice under uncertainty. The mounting evidence against the model has led to a growing tension between those who view economic analysis as the description and prediction of what they consider to be rational behavior and those who view it as the description and prediction of observed behavior. Let us turn now to this evidence.
Violations Of Linearity In Tile Probabilities
The Allais Paradox And "Fanning Out"
One of the earliest and best-known examples of systematic violation of linearity in the probabilities (or, equivalently, of the independence axiom) is the well-known Allais paradox.19 This problem involves obtaining the individual's preferred option from each of the following two pairs of gambles (readers who have never seen this problem may want to circle their own choices before proceeding):
versus | ||
and | ||
versus |
Defining {x1, x2, x3} = {$0;$1 million;$5 million}, these four gambles are seen to form to a parallelogram in the (p1, p3) triangle (Figures 4a and 4b). Under the expected utility hypothesis, therefore, a preference for a1 in the first pair would indicate that the individual's indifference curves were relatively steep (as in Figure 4a), which would imply a preference for a4 in the second pair. In the alternative case of relatively flat indifference curves, the gambles a2 and as would be preferred.20 Yet, such researchers as Allais (1953, 1979a), Morrison (1967), Raiffa (1968), and Slovic and Tversky (1974) have found that the most common choice has been for a1 in the first pair and as in the second, which implies that indifference curves are not parallel but rather fan out, as in Figure 4b.
One of the criticisms of this evidence has been that individuals whose choices violated the independence axiom would "correct" themselves once the nature of their violations were revealed by an application of the above coin-flip argument.21 Thus, although even Savage chose a1 and a3 when he was first presented with this problem, upon reflection, he concluded that these preferences were in error.22 Although his own reaction was undoubtedly sincere, the prediction that individuals would invarialy, react in such a manner has not been sustained in direct empirical testing. In experiments in which subjects were asked to respond to Allais-type problems and then presented with written arguments both for and against the expected utility position, neither MacCrimmon (1968), Moskowitz (1974), nor Slovic and Tversky (1974) found predominant net swings toward the expected utility choices.23
Additional Evidence Of Fanning Out
Although the Allais paradox was originally dismissed as an isolated example, it is now known to be a special case of a general empirical pattern that is called the common consequence effect. This effect involves pairs of probability mixtures of the form where P involves outcomes both greater and less than x, and P** stochastically dominates P*.24 Although the independence axiom clearly implies choices of either b1 and b3 (if x is preferred to P) or b2 and b4 (if P is preferred to x), researchers have again found a tendency for subjects to choose b1 in the first pair and b4 in the second.25 When the distributions P, P*, and P** are each over a common outcome set {x1, x2, x3} that includes x, the prospects b1, b2, b3, and b4 will again form a parallelogram in the
versus | ||
and | ||
versus |
(p1, p3) triangle, and a choice of b1 and b4 again implies indifference curves that fan out as in Figure 4b.
The intuition behind this phenomenon can be described in terms of the coin-flip scenario noted earlier. According to the independence axiom, preferences over what would occur in the event of heads should not depend upon what would occur in the event of tails. In fact, however, they may well depend on what would otherwise happen.26 The common consequence effect states that the better off individuals would be in the event of mils (in the sense of stochastic dominance), the more risk averse they become over what they would receive in the event of heads. Intuitively, if the distribution P** in the pair {b1, b2} involves very high outcomes, an individual may prefer not to bear further risk in the unlucky event that he or she does not receive it, and prefer instead the sure outcome x over the distribution P in this event (i.e., choose b1 over b2). If P* in {b3, b4} involves very low outcomes, however, an individual may be more willing to bear risk in the (lucky) event that he or she doesn't receive it, and prefer the lottery P to the outcome x in this case (i.e., choose b4 over b3). Note that it is not the individual's beliefs regarding the probabilities in P that are affected here, merely his or her willingness to bear them.27
A second class of systematic violations, stemming from another early example of Allais (1953), is known as the common ratio effect. This phenomenon involves pairs of prospects of the form where p > q, 0 < X < Y and 0 < α < 1; it includes the "certainty effect" of Kahneman and Tversky (1979) and the ingenious "Bergen paradox" of Hagen (1979) as special cases.28 Setting {x1, x2, x3} = {0, X, Y} and plotting these prospects in the (p1, p3) triangle, the segments and are seen to be parallel (as in Figure 5a), so that the expected utility model again predicts choices of c1 and c3 (if the individual's indifference curves are steep) or c2 and c4 (if they are flat). Yet, experimental studies have found a systematic tendency for choices to depart from these predictions in the direction of preferring c1 and c4,29 which again suggests that indifference curves fan out, as in the figure. In a variation on this approach, Kahneman and Tversky (1979) replaced the gains of $X and $Y in the above gambles with losses of these magnitudes and found a tendency to depart from expected utility in the direction of c2 and c3. Defining {x1, x2, x3} as {-Y, -X, 0} (to maintain the ordering x1 < x2 < x3) and plotting these gambles in Figure 5b, a choice of c2 and c3 is again seen to imply that indifference curves fan out. Finally, Battalio, Kagel, and MacDonald (1985) found that laboratory rats choosing among gambles that involved substantial variations in their actual daily food intake also exhibited this pattern of choices.
versus | ||
and | ||
versus |
A third class of evidence stems from the elicitation method described in the previous section. In particular, the reader should note that there is no reason why the mixture probability must be 1/2, as in the earlier example. Picking any other value—say obtaining the individual's certainty equivalent of the gamble offering a 1/4 chance of M and a 3/4 chance of 0 will lead to the property that ; in addition, just as in the previous case of , the procedure using (or any other fixed value) can also be continued to (in the limit) completely recover U(·).
Although this procedure should recover the same (normalized) utility function for any value of the mixture probability , such researchers as Karmarkar (1974, 1978) and McCord and de Neufville (1983, 1984) have found a tendency for higher values of to lead to the "recovery" of higher valued utility functions (Figure 6a). By illustrating the gambles used to obtain the certainty equivalents ξ1, ξ2, and ξ3 for the mixture probability , for and , for Figure 6b shows that, as with the common consequence and common ratio effects, this utility evaluation effect is precisely what would be expected from an individual whose indifference curves departed from expected utility by fanning out.30
Non-Expected Utility Models Of Preferences
The systematic nature of these departures from linearity in the probabilities have led several researchers to generalize the expected utility model by positing nonlinear functional forms for the individual preference function. Some examples of such forms and researchers who have studied them are given in Table 1. Many (though not all) of these forms are flexible enough to exhibit the properties of stochastic dominance preference, risk aversion/risk preference, and fanning out, and the Chew/MacCrimmon/Fishburn and Quiggin forms have proven to be particularly useful both theoretically and empirically. Additional analyses of the above forms can be found in Chew, Karni, and Safra (1987); Fishburn (1982, 1984a,b); Röell (1987); Segal (1984, 1987); and Yaari (1987). For general surveys of these models, see Machina (1983a), Sugden (1986), and Weber and Camerer (1987).
Although such forms allow for the modeling of preferences that are more general than those allowed by the expected utility hypothesis, each requires a different set of conditions on its component functions v(·), p(·), or g(·) for the properties of stochastic dominance preference, risk aversion/risk preference, comparative risk aversion, and so forth. In particular, the standard expected utility results that link properties of the function U(·) to such aspects of behavior generally will not extend to the corresponding properties of the function v(·) in the above forms. Does this imply that the study of non-expected utility preferences requires one to abandon the vast body of theoretical results and intuition that have been developed within the expected utility framework?
Fortunately, the answer is no. An alternative approach to the analysis of non-expected utility preferences proceeds not by adopting a specific nonlinear function but by considering nonlinear functions in general , and using calculus to extend results from expected utility theory in the same manner in which it is typically used to extend results involving linear functions. (Readers who are not interested in the details of this approach may wish to skip ahead to the next section.31)
Specifically, let us consider the set of all probability distributions P = (p1,... ,pn) over a fixed outcome set {x1, ..., xn}, so that the expected utility preference function can be written as V(P) = V(p1, ..., pn) = U(x1)p1 +... + U(xn)pn. Let us also think of U(xi) not as a "utility level" but rather as the coefficient of pi = prob( xi) in this linear function. If these coefficients are plotted against xi as in Figure 7, the expected utility results of the previous section can be stated as:
- Stochastic Dominance Preference: V(·) will exhibit global stochastic dominance preference if and only if the coefficients {U(xi)} are increasing in xi, as in Figure 7.
- Comparative Risk Aversion: The expected utility preference function V*(P) = U*(x1)p1 + ... + U*(xn)pn will be at least as risk averse as v(·) if and only if the coefficients {U*(xi)} are at least as concave in xi as {U(xi)}.33
Now, let us consider the case in which the individual's preference function V(P) = V(p1, ... pn) is not linear (i.e., not expected utility) but at least differentiable, and let us consider its partial derivatives Some probability distribution P0 can be chosen and these values plotted against xi. If they are increasing in xi, it is clear that any infinitesimal stochastically dominating shift from
P0, such as a decrease in some pi and matching increase in pi+1, will be preferred. If they are concave in xi, any infinitesimal mean preserving spread, such as a drop in pi and (mean preserving) rise in Pi-1 and Pi+1, will make the individual worse off. In light of this correspondence between the coefficients {U(xi)} of the expected utility preference function V(·) and the partial derivatives of the non-expected utility preference function V(·), as the individual's local utility indices at P0.
Of course, the above results will only hold exactly for infinitesimal shifts from the distribution P0. However, another result from standard calculus can be exploited to show how ''expected utility" results may be applied to the exact global analysis of non-expected utility preferences. The reader should recall that, in many cases, a differentiable function will exhibit a specific global property if and only if that property is exhibited by its linear approximations at each point. For example, a differentiable function will be globally nondecreasing if and only if its linear approximation at each point is nonnegative. In fact, most of the fundamental properties of risk attitudes and their expected utility characterizations are precisely of this type. In particular, the following can be shown:
- Stochastic Dominance Preference: A non-expected utility preference function V(·) will exhibit global stochastic dominance preference if and only if its local utility indices are increasing in xi at each distribution P.
- Risk Aversion: V(·) will exhibit global risk aversion if and only if its local utility indices are concave in xi at each distribution P.
- Comparative Risk Aversion: The preference function V*(·) will be globally at least as risk averse34 as V(·) if and only if its local utility indices are at least as concave in xi as at each P.
Figures 8a and 8b are a graphic illustration of this approach for the outcome set {x1, x2, x3}. Here, the solid curves denote the indifference curves of the non-expected utility preference function V(P). The parallel lines near the lottery P0 denote the tangent "expected utility" indifference curves that correspond to the local utility indices at P0. As always with differentiable functions, an infinitesimal change in the probabilities at P0 will be preferred if and only if it would be preferred by this tangent linear (i.e., expected utility) approximation. Figure 8b illustrates the above "risk aversion" result. It is clear that these indifference curves will be globally risk averse (averse to mean preserving spreads) if and only if these are everywhere steeper than the dashed iso-expected value lines. However, this is equivalent to all of their tangents being steeper than these lines, which in turn is equivalent to all of their local expected utility approximations being steeper—or, in other words, to the local utility indices being concave in xi at each distribution P.
My fellow researchers and I have shown how this and similar techniques can be applied to further extend the results of expected utility theory to the case of non-expected utility preferences, to characterize and explore the implications of preferences that "fan out," and to conduct new and more general analyses of economic behavior under uncertainty.35 Still, although I feel that they constitute a useful and promising response to the phenomenon of nonlinearities in the probabilities, these models do not provide solutions to the more problematic empirical phenomena described in the following sections.
The Preference Reversal Phenomenon
The Evidence
The finding now known as the preference reversal phenomenon was initially reported by psychologists Lichtenstein and Slovic (1971). In this study, subjects were first presented with a number of pairs of bets and asked to choose one bet out of each pair. Each of these pairs took the following form:
versus |
where X and Y are respectively greater than x and y, p is greater than q, and Y is greater than X (the names "P-bet" and "$-bet" come from the greater probability of winning in the first bet and greater possible gain in the second). In some cases, x and y took on small negative values. The subjects were next asked to "value'' (state certainty equivalents for) each of these bets. The different valuation methods that were used consisted of (a) asking subjects to state their minimum selling price for each bet if they were to own it, (b) asking them to state their maximum bid price for each bet if they were to buy it, and (c) the elicitation procedure of Becker, DeGroot, and Marschak (1964), in which it is in a subject's best interest to reveal his or her true certainty equivalent.36 In the latter case, real money was in fact used.
The expected utility model, as well as each of the non-expected utility models of the previous section, clearly implies that the bet that is actually chosen out of each pair will also be the one that is assigned the higher certainty equivalent.37 However, Lichtenstein and Slovic (1971) found a systematic tendency to violate this prediction in the direction of choosing the P-bet in a direct choice but assigning a higher value to the $-bet. In one experiment, for example, 127 out of 173 subjects assigned a higher sell price to the S-bet in every pair in which the P-bet was chosen. Similar findings were obtained by Lindman (1971) and, in an interesting variation on the usual experimental setting, by Lichtenstein and Slovic (1973) in a Las Vegas casino where customers actually staked (and hence sometimes lost) their own money. In another real-money experiment, Mowen and Gentry (1980) found that groups who could discuss their (joint) decisions were if anything more likely than individuals to exhibit the phenomenon.
Although these above studies involved deliberate variations in design in order to check for the robustness of this phenomenon, they were nevertheless received skeptically by economists, who perhaps not unnaturally felt they had more at stake than psychologists in this type of finding. In an admitted attempt to "discredit" this work, economists Grether and Plott (1979) designed a pair of experiments in which they corrected for issues of incentives, income effects,38 strategic considerations, the ability to indicate indifference, and so forth. They expected that the experiments would not generate this phenomenon, but they nonetheless found it in both. Further design modifications by Pommerehne, Schneider, and Zweifel (1982) and Reilly (1982) yielded the same results. Finally, the phenomenon has been found to persist (although in mitigated form) even when subjects are allowed to engage in experimental market transactions involving the gambles (Knez and Smith, 1987), or when the experimenter is able to act as an arbitrager and make money from such reversals (Berg, Dickhaut, and O'Brien, 1983).
Two Interpretations Of This Phenomenon
How one interprets these findings depends on whether one adopts the world view of an economist or a psychologist. An economist would reason as follows: Each individual possesses a unique underlying preference ordering over objects (in this case lotteries), and information about this preference ordering can be gleaned from either direct choice questions or (properly designed) valuation questions.39 Someone exhibiting the preference reversal phenomenon is therefore indicating that (a) they are indifferent regarding the choice between the P-bet and some sure amount ξp (b) they strictly prefer the P-bet to the $-bet, and (c) they are indifferent regarding the choice between the $-bet and an amount ξ$ greater than ξp. Assuming that they in fact prefer ξ$ to the lesser amount ξp, this implies that their preferences over these four objects are cyclic or intransitive.
Psychologists, on the other hand, would deny the premise of an common underlying mechanism generating both choice and valuation behavior. Rather, they view choice and valuation (even different forms of valuation) as distinct processes, subject possibly to different influences. In other words, individuals exhibit what are termed response mode effects. Excellent discussions and empirical examinations of this phenomenon and its implications for the elicitation of both probabilistic beliefs and utility functions can be found in Hogarth (1975, 1980); Hershey, Kunreuther, and Schoemaker (1982); Slovic, Fischhoff, and Lichtenstein (1982); Hershey and Schoemaker (1985); and MacCrimmon and Wehrung (1986). To report how the response mode study of Slovic and Lichtenstein (1968) actually led them to predict the preference reversal phenomenon, I can do no better than to quote the authors themselves:
The impetus for this study [Lichtenstein and Slavic (1971)] was our observation in our earlier 1968 article that choices among pairs of gambles appeared to be influenced primarily by probabilities of winning and losing, whereas buying and selling prices were primarily determined by the dollar amounts that could be won or lost. . .. In our 1971 article, we argued that, if the information in a gamble is processed differently when making choices and setting prices, it should be possible to construct pairs of gambles such that people would choose one member of the pair but set a higher price on the other. [Slovic and Lichtenstein (1983:597)]
Implications Of The Economic World View
The issue of intransitivity is new neither to economics nor to choice under uncertainty. May (1954), for example, observed intransitivities in pairwise rankings of three alternative marriage partners, in which each candidate was rated highly in two of three attributes (intelligence, looks, wealth) and low in the third. In an uncertain context, Blyth (1972) has adapted this approach to construct a set of random variables () such that prob() = prob() = prob() = 2/3, so that individuals making pairwise choices on the basis of these probabilities would also be intransitive. In addition to the preference reversal phenomenon, Edwards (1954a)40 and Tversky (1969) have also observed intransitivities in preferences over risky prospects. On the other hand, researchers have also shown that many aspects of economic theory, in particular the existence of demand functions and of general equilibrium, are surprisingly robust to the phenomenon of intransitivity (Sonnenschein, 1971; Mas-Colell (1974); Shafer, 1974, 1976; Kim and Richter, 1986; Epstein, 1987).
In any event, economists have begun to develop and analyze models of nontransitive preferences over lotteries. The leading example of this is the "regret theory" model developed independently by Bell (1982, 1983) (see also Bell and Raiffa [1980]), Fishburn [1981, 1982, 1984a,b], and Loomes and Sugden [1982, 1983a,b]). In this model of pairwise choice the von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function U(x) is replaced by a regret/rejoice function r(x,y) that represents the level of satisfaction (or, if negative, dissatisfaction) the individual would experience if he or she were to receive the outcome x when the alternative choice would have yielded the outcome y (this function is assumed to satisfy r(x,y) = -r(y,x) for all values of x and y). In choosing between statistically independent gambles P = (p1,..., pn) and over a common outcome set {x1,...,xn}, the individual will choose P* if the expected value of the function r(x,y) is positive and P if it is negative41 (Once again, readers who wish to skip the mathematical details of this approach may proceed to the following subsection.)
It is interesting to note that when the regret/rejoice function takes the special form r(x,y) = U(x) - U(y) this model reduces to the expected utility model.42 In general, however, such an individual will neither be an expected utility maximizer nor have transitive preferences.
Yet, this intransitivity does not prevent the graphing of such preferences or even the application of the "expected utility" analysis to them. To see the former, let us consider the case in which the individual is facing alternative independent lotteries over a common outcome set {x1,x2,x3}, so that the triangle diagram may again be used to illustrate their "indifference curves," which will appear as in Figure 9. In such a case, it is important to understand what is and is not still true of these indifference curves. The curve through P will still correspond to the points (i.e., lotteries) that are indifferent to P, and it will still divide the points that are strictly preferred to P (the points in the direction of the arrow) from the ones to which P is strictly preferred. Furthermore, if (as in the figure) P* lies above the indifference curve through P, then P will lie below the indifference curve through P* (i.e., the individual's ranking of P and P* will be unambiguous). Unlike indifference curves for transitive preferences, however, these curves will cross,43 and preferences over the lotteries P, P*, and P** are seen to form an intransitive cycle. In regions in which the indifference curves do not cross (such as near the origin), however, the individual will be indistinguishable from someone with transitive (albeit non-expected utility) preferences.
To see how expected utility results can be extended to this nontransitive framework, let us fix a lottery P = (p1,...,pn) and consider the question of when an (independent) lottery will be preferred or not preferred to P. Defining the "utility function" , it is possible to show that P* will be preferred to P if and only if —in other words, if and only if P* implies a higher expectation of the function than does P.44 Thus, if is increasing in x for all lotteries P, the individual will exhibit global stochastic dominance preference; if is concave in x for all P, the individual will exhibit global risk aversion, even though he or she is not necessarily transitive (these conditions will clearly be satisfied if r(x,y) is increasing and concave in x).45 The analytics of expected utility theory are robust, indeed.
Bell, Raiffa, Loomes, Sugden, and Fishburn have also shown how specific assumptions about the form of the regret/rejoice function will generate the common consequence effect, the common ratio effect, the preference reversal phenomenon, and other observed properties of choice over lotteries.46 The theoretical and empirical prospects for this approach seem quite impressive.
Implications Of The Psychological World View
On the other hand, how should economists respond if it turns out that the psychologists are right and that the preference reversal phenomenon really is generated by some form of response mode effect (or effects)? In that case, the first thing to do would be to try to determine if there were analogues of such effects in real-world economic situations.47 Will individuals behave differently when they are determining their valuation of an object (e.g., reservation bid on a used car) than they will when reacting to a fixed and nonnegotiable price for the same object? Because a proper test of this question would require correcting for any possible strategic or information-theoretic (e.g., signaling) issues, it would not be a simple undertaking. However, in light of the experimental evidence, I feel it is crucial that it be attempted.
Let us say that it was found that response mode effects did not occur outside of the laboratory. In that case, we scientists could rest more easily, although we could not forget about such issues completely: experimenters testing other economic theories and models (e.g., auctions) would have to be forever mindful of the possible influence of the particular response mode used in their experimental design.
On the other hand, what if response mode effects were found out in the field? In such circumstances, we would want to determine, perhaps by going back to the laboratory, whether the rest of economic theory remained valid—provided the response mode were held constant. If this were true, then with further evidence on exactly how the response mode mattered, we could presumably incorporate it into existing theories as a new independent variable. Because response modes tend to be constant within specific economic models (e.g., quantity responses to fixed prices in competitive markets, valuation announcements—truthful or otherwise—in auctions, etc.), we should expect most of the testable implications of this approach to appear as cross-institutional predictions, such as systematic violations of the various equivalency results involving prices versus quantities, or second price/sealed bid versus oral English auctions. I feel that the new results and implications for our theories of institutions and mechanisms would be exciting indeed.48
Framing Effects
Evidence
In addition to response mode effects, psychologists have uncovered an even more disturbing phenomenon: namely, that alternative means of representing or "framing" probabilistically equivalent choice problems will lead to systematic differences in choice. An early example of this phenomenon is reported by Slovic (1969b), who found, for example, that offering a gain or loss contingent on the joint occurrence of four independent events with probability p elicited responses different from offering it on the occurrence of a single event with probability p4 (all underlying probabilities were stated explicitly). In comparison with the single-event case, making a gain contingent on the joint occurrence of events was found to make it more attractive; making a loss contingent on the joint occurrence of events made it more unattractive.49
In another study, Payne and Braunstein (1971) used pairs of gambles of the type illustrated in Figure 10. Each of the gambles in the figure, known as a duplex gamble, involves spinning the pointers on both its "gain wheel" (on the left) and its "loss wheel" (on the right), with the individual face of wealth variations has also been observed in several experimental studies.51
Markowitz (1952:155) also suggested that certain circumstances may cause the individual's reference point to deviate temporarily from current wealth. If these circumstances include the manner in which a given problem is verbally described, then differing risk attitudes over gains and losses can receiving the sum of the resulting amounts. Thus, an individual choosing gamble A would win $.40 with probability .3 (i.e., if the pointer in the gain wheel landed up and the pointer in the loss wheel landed down), would lose $.40 with probability .2 (if the pointers landed in the reverse positions), and would break even with probability .5 (if the pointers landed either both up or both down). An examination of gamble B reveals that it has an identical underlying distribution; thus, subjects should be indifferent regarding a choice between the two gambles, regardless of their risk preferences. Payne and Braunstein, however, found that individuals in fact chose between such pairs (and indicated nontrivial strengths of preference) in manners that were systematically affected by the attributes of the component wheels. When the probability of winning in the gain wheel was greater than the probability of losing in the loss wheel for each gamble (as in the figure), subjects tended to choose the gamble whose gain wheel yielded the greater probability of a gain (gamble A). In cases in which the probabilities of losing in the loss wheels were greater than the probabilities of winning in the gain wheels, subjects tended to choose the gamble with the lower probability of losing in the loss wheel.
Finally, although the gambles in Figure 10 possess identical underlying distributions, continuity suggests that worsening of the terms of the preferred gamble could result in a pair of nonequivalent duplex gambles in which the individual will actually choose the one with the stochastically dominated underlying distribution. In an experiment in which subjects were allowed to construct their own duplex gambles by choosing one from a pair of prospects involving gains and one from a pair of prospects involving losses, stochastically dominated combinations were indeed, chosen (Tversky and Kahneman, 1981; Kahneman and Tversky, 1984).50
A second class of framing effects exploits the phenomenon of a reference point. Theoretically, the variable that enters an individual's yon Neumann-Morgenstern utility functions should be total (i.e., final) wealth, and gambles phrased in terms of gains and losses should be combined with current wealth and reexpressed as distributions over final wealth levels before being evaluated. However, economists since Markowitz (1952) have observed that risk attitudes over gains and losses are more stable than can be explained by a fixed utility function over final wealth, and have suggested that the utility function might be best defined in terms of changes from the "reference point" of current wealth. The stability of risk attitudes in the lead to different choices, depending on the exact description. A simple example of this, from Kahneman and Tversky (1979:273), involves the following two questions:
In addition to whatever you own, you have been given 1,000 (Israeli pounds). You are now asked to choose between a 1/2:1/2 chance of a gain of 1,000 or 0 or a sure chance of a gain of 500.
and
In addition to whatever you own, you have been given 2,000. You are now asked to choose between a 1/2:1/2 chance of a loss of 1,000 or 0 or a sure loss of 500.
These two problems involve identical distributions over final wealth. When put to two different groups of subjects, however, 84 percent chose the sure gain in the first problem, but 69 percent chose the 1/2:1/2 gamble in the second. A nonmonetary version of this type of example, from Tversky and Kahneman (1981:453), posits the following scenario:
Imagine that the U.S. is preparing for the outbreak of an unusual Asian disease, which is expected to kill 600 people. Two alternative programs to combat the disease have been proposed. Assume that the exact scientific estimate of the consequences of the programs are as follows:
If Program A is adopted, 200 people will be saved.
If Program B is adopted, there is 1/3 probability that 600 people will be saved, and 2/3 probability that no people will be saved.
Seventy-two percent of the subjects who were presented with this form of the question chose program A. A second group was given the same initial information, but the descriptions of the programs were changed to read (p. 453):
If Program C is adopted 400 people will die.
If Program D is adopted there is 1/3 probability that nobody will die, and 2/3 probability that 600 people will die.
Although this statement once again implies a problem that is identical to the former one, 78 percent of the respondents chose program D.
In other studies, Schoemaker and Kunreuther (1979); Hershey and Schoemaker (1980b); Kahneman and Tversky (1982, 1984); Hershey, Kunreuther, and Schoemaker (1982); McNeil et al. (1982); and Slovic, Fischhoff, and Lichtenstein (1982) have found that subjects' choices in otherwise identical problems will depend on whether the choices are phrased as decisions about whether to gamble or to insure, whether the statistical information for different therapies is presented in terms of cumulative survival probabilities over time or cumulative mortality probabilities over time, and so forth (see also the additional references in Tversky and Kahneman [1981] as well as the examples of this phenomenon in nonstochastic situations given in Thaler [1980, 1985]).
In a final class of examples, not based on reference point effects, Moskowitz (1974) and Keller (1985) found that the proportion of subjects that choose in conformance with or in violation of the independence axiom in examples like the Allais paradox was significantly affected by whether the problems were described in the standard matrix form (e.g., Raiffa, 1968:7), in a decision tree form, or as minimally structured written statements. Interestingly enough, the form that was judged to be the "clearest representation" by the majority of Moskowitz's subjects (the tree form) led to the lowest degree of consistency with the independence axiom, the highest proportion of Allais-type (i.e., fanning out) choices, and the highest persistency rate of these choices (1974:234, 237-38).
Two Issues Regarding Framing
The replicability and pervasiveness of the above group of examples is indisputable. Their implications for economic modeling involve two issues (at least). The first is whether these experimental observations possess any analogue outside of the laboratory. Real-world decision problems are never as neatly packaged as those that appear on experimental questionnaires; thus, monitoring such effects would not be as straightforward. This difficulty in monitoring does not mean that such efforts do not exist, however, or that they cannot be objectively observed or quantitatively measured. The real-world example that comes most quickly to mind, and is presumably of no small importance to the involved parties, is whether gasoline price differentials should be represented as "cash discounts" or "credit surcharges." Similarly, Russo, Krieser, and Miyashita (1975) and Russo (1977) found that the practice and even the method of displaying unit price information in supermarkets (information that allowed consumers to calculate for themselves) affected both the level and distribution of consumer expenditures. The empirical marketing literature is no doubt replete with findings that could legitimately be interpreted as real-world framing effects.
The second, more difficult issue is that of the independent observability of the particular frame that an individual will adopt in a given problem. In the duplex gamble and matrix/decision tree/written statement examples of the previous section, the different frames seem unambiguously determined by the form of presentation. In instances in which framing involves the choice of a reference point, however, instances that presumably include the majority of real-world cases, this point might not be objectively determined by the form of presentation. Rather, it might be chosen differently and, what is worse, unobservably, by each individual.52 In a particularly thorough and insightful study, Fischhoff (1983) presented subjects with a written decision problem that allowed for different choices of a reference point. The study went on to explore different ways of predicting which flame individuals would adopt in order to be able to predict their actual choices. Although the majority choice of subjects was consistent with what would appear to be the most appropriate frame, Fischhoff noted ''the absence of any relation within those studies between [separately elicited] frame preference and option preference." Indeed, to the extent that frame preferences varied across his experiments, they did so inversely to the incidence of the predicted choice (Fischhoff, 1983:115-116).53 If such problems can occur in predicting responses to specific written questions in the laboratory, imagine how they could plague the modeling of real-world choice behavior.
Framing Effects And Economic Analysis: Has This Problem Already Been Solved?
What response is appropriate if it turns out that flaming actually is a real-world phenomenon of economic relevance and, in particular, if individuals' frames cannot always be observed? I would argue that the means of responding to this issue can already be found in the "tool box" of existing economic analysis.
Let us consider first the case in which the flame of a particular economic decision problem (even though it should not matter from the point of view of standard theory), can at least be independently and objectively observed. I believe that, in fact, economists have already solved such a problem in their treatment of the phenomenon of "uninformative advertising." Although it is hard to give a formal definition of this term, it is widely felt that economic theory is hard put to explain a large portion of current advertising in terms of traditional informational considerations.54 This constraint, however, has hardly led economists to abandon classical consumer theory. Rather, models of uninformative advertising proceed by quantifying this variable (e.g., air time) and treating it as an additional independent variable in the utility function, the demand function, or both. Standard results like the Slutsky equation need not be abandoned but rather reinterpreted as properties of demand functions holding this new variable constant. The degree of advertising itself is determined as a maximizing variable on the part of the firm (given some cost curve) and is thus subject to standard comparative static analysis.
In cases in which decision frames can be observed, framing effects presumably can be modeled in an analogous manner. To do so, one would begin by adopting a method of quantifying—or at least of categorizing—frames. The activity of the second step, some of which has of course already been done, would be to study both the effect of this new independent variable holding the standard economic variables constant, and, conversely, to retest standard economic theories in conditions in which the frame was carefully held in a fixed position. With any luck, one would find that, holding the frame constant, the Slutsky equation still held.
The next step in any given modeling situation would be to discover "who determines the frame." If (as with advertising) it is the firm, then the effect of the frame on consumer demand, and hence on the firm's profits, can be incorporated into the firm's maximization problem. The choice of the frame, as well as the other relevant variables (e.g., prices and quantities), can be simultaneously determined and subjected to comparative static analysis just as in the case of uninformative advertising.
A seemingly more difficult case is when the individual chooses the frame (for example, a reference point), and this choice cannot be observed. Although findings of Fischhoff (1983) should be kept in mind, let us assume that this choice is at least systematic in the sense that the consumer will join fly choose the frame and make the subsequent decision in a way that maximizes a "utility function" that depends both on the decision and on the choice of frame. In other words, individuals make their choices as part of a joint maximization problem, the other component of which (the choice of frame or reference point) cannot be observed.
Such models are hardly new to economic analysis. Indeed, most economic models presuppose that the agent is simultaneously maximizing his or her choices with respect to variables other than the ones being studied. When assumptions are made on the individual's joint preferences over the unobserved and observed variables, the well-known theory of induced preferences can be used to derive testable implications on choice behavior over the observables.55 With a little more knowledge on exactly how frames are chosen, such an approach could presumably be applied here as well.
The above remarks should not be taken as implying that the problems of framing in economic analysis have already been solved or that there is no need to adapt and, if necessary, abandon standard economic models in light of this phenomenon. Rather, the remarks reflect the view that when psychologists are able to present enough systematic evidence on how these effects operate, economists will be able to respond appropriately.
Other Issues: Is Probability Theory Relevant?
The Manipulation Of Subjective Probabilities
The evidence discussed so far has consisted primarily of cases in which subjects were presented with explicit (i.e., "objective") probabilities as part of their decision problems and the models that addressed these phenomena possessed the corresponding property of being defined over objective probability distributions. There is extensive evidence, however, that when individuals have to estimate or revise probabilities for themselves, they will make systematic mistakes in doing so.
The psychological literature on the processing of probabilistic information is much too large even to summarize here. Yet, it is worth noting that experimenters have uncovered several "heuristics" used by subjects that can lead to predictable errors in the formation and manipulation of subjective probabilities. Kahneman and Tversky (1973), Bar-s (1974), and Grether (1980), for example, all found that probability updating systematically departs from Bayes' law in the direction of underweighting prior information and overweighting the "representativeness" of the current sample. In a related phenomenon termed the "law of small numbers," Tversky and Kahneman (1971) found that individuals overestimated the probability of drawing a perfectly representative sample out of a heterogeneous population. Finally, Bar-Hillel (1973), Tversky and Kahneman (1983), and others have found systematic biases in the formation of the probabilities of conjunctions of both independent and nonindependent events. For surveys, discussions, and examples of the psychological literature on the formation and handling of probabilities, see Edwards, Lindman, and Savage (1963); Edwards (1971); Slovic and Lichtenstein (1971); Tversky and Kahneman (1974); and Grether (1978), as well as the collections in Acta Psychologica (December 1970); Kahneman, Slovic, and Tversky (1982); and Arkes and Hammond (1986). For examples of how economists have responded to some of these issues, see Arrow (1982), Viscusi (1985a,b) and the references cited there.
The Existence Of Subjective Probabilities
The evidence referred to above indicates that when individuals are asked to formulate probabilities they seldom do it correctly. These findings may be rendered moot, however, by evidence that suggests that when individuals making decisions under uncertainty are not explicitly asked to form subjective probabilities they might not do it at all.
In one of a class of examples developed by Ellsberg (1961), subjects were presented with a pair of urns: the first contained 50 red balls and 50 black balls, and the second also contained 100 red and black balls but in an unknown proportion. When faced with the choice of staking a prize on (R1) drawing a red ball from the first urn, (R2) drawing a red ball from the second urn, (B1) drawing a black ball from the first urn, or (B2) drawing a black ball from the second urn, a majority of subjects strictly preferred (R1) over (R2) and strictly preferred (B1) over (B2). It is clear that there can exist no subjectively assigned of probabilities p : (1 - p) of drawing a red versus a black ball from the second urn—not even 1/2:1/2, that can simultaneously generate both of these strict preferences. Similar behavior in this and related problems has been observed by Raiffa (1961), Becker and Brownson (1964), MacCrimmon (1965), Slovic and Tversky (1974), and MacCrimmon and Larsson (1979).56
Life (And Economic Analysis) Without Probability Theory
One response to this type of phenomenon as been to suppose that individuals "slant" whatever subjective probabilities they might otherwise form in a manner that reflects the amount of confidence or ambiguity associated with them (Fellner, 1961, 1963; Becker and Brownson, 1964; Brewer and Fellner, 1965; Fishburn, 1985, 1986; Hogarth and Kunreuther, 1985, 1986; and Einhorn and Hogarth, 1986). In the case of complete ignorance regarding probabilities, Arrow and Hurwicz (1972), Maskin (1979), and others have presented axioms that imply such principles as ranking options solely on the basis of their best or worst possible outcomes or (both) (e.g., maximin, maximax), the unweighted average of their outcomes ("principle of insufficient reason"), or similar criteria.57 Finally generalizations of expected utility theory that drop the standard additivity or compounding laws of probability theory (or both) have been developed by Schmeidler (1989) and Segal (1987).
Although the above models may well capture aspects of actual decision processes, analytically the most useful approach to choice in the presence of uncertainty but the absence of probabilities is the so-called state-preference model of Arrow (1953/1964), Debreu (1959), and Hirshleifer (1965, 1966).58
In this model, uncertainty is represented by a set of mutually exclusive and exhaustive states of nature S = {si}. This partition of all possible unfoldings of the future could be either coarse, such as the pair of states {it rains here tomorrow, it does not rain here tomorrow}, or else very fine (so that the definition of a state might read "it rains here tomorrow and the temperature at Gibraltar is 75 degrees at noon and the price of gold in London is below $700 per ounce"). Note that it is neither feasible nor desirable to capture all conceivable sources of uncertainty when specifying the set of states for a given problem. It is not feasible because no matter how finely the states are defined, there will always be some other random criterion on which to further divide them; it is not desirable because such criteria may affect neither individuals' preferences nor their opportunities. Rather, the key requirements are that the states be mutually exclusive and exhaustive so that exactly one will be realized, and that the extent to which the individual is able to influence their probabilities (if at all) be explicitly specified.
Given a fixed (and, let us say, finite) set of states, the objects of choice in this framework consist of alternative state-payoff bundles , each of which specifies the outcome the individual will receive in every possible state. When, for example, the outcomes are monetary payoffs, state-payoff bundles take the form (c1,...,cn), where ci denotes the payoff the individual will receive should state i occur. In the case of exactly two states of nature, this set can be represented set by the points in the (c1,c2) plane. Because bundles of the form (c, c) represent prospects that yield the same payoff in each state of nature, the 45-degree line in this plane is known as the certainty line.
Now, if the individual happens to assign some set of probabilities {pi} to the states {si}, each bundle (c1,...,cn) will imply a specific probability distribution over the payoffs, and his or her preferences could be inferred (i.e., indifference curves) over state-payoff bundles.59 Yet bemuse these bundles are defined directly over the respective states and without reference to any probabilities, it is possible to speak of preferences over such bundles without making any assumptions regarding the coherency, or even the existence, of probabilistic beliefs. Researchers such as those listed above, as well as Yaari (1969), Diamond and Yaari (1972), and Mishan (1976), have used this indifference curve-based approach to derive results from individual demand behavior through general equilibrium in a context that requires neither the expected utility hypothesis nor the existence or commonality of subjective probabilities. In other words, life without probability theory does not imply life without economic analysis.60
Implications For Private And Public Decision Making
Fifteen years ago, a decision analyst who was advising an individual, firm, or government agency in a choice under uncertainty might use something like the following stylized procedure.
- 1.
Collect as much information as possible about the decision, and construct an explicit list of the currently (and potentially) available options.
- 2.
Assess the decision maker's (or, alternatively, the "experts' ") subjective probability distributions over consequences implied by each option.
- 3.
Evaluate the decision maker's (or, alternatively, "society's') preferences regarding the alternative consequences, including their attitudes toward risk (in other words, assess their von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function).
- 4.
Determine the option that would yield the highest (individual or social) expected utility.61
Of course, the consequences might involve several dimensions (requiring the assessment of a multivariate utility function),62 or the experts might disagree on the probabilities (requiring some form of consensus, aggregation, or pooling of beliefs).63 Nevertheless, researchers working on these aspects remained confident of the validity of this overall (expected utility-based) approach.
Should the developments surveyed in this paper change the way private decision analysts or public decision makers go about their jobs? Do they imply new or different business or governmental responsibilities in keeping customers or citizens informed of any voluntary (or involuntary) risks they may be facing? The following section discusses some of the issues that these new developments raise.
Implications For Private-Sector Decision Analysis
How should private-sector decision analysts adapt their procedures in light of these new empirical findings and theoretical models? It is hard to see how step 1 (formulating the options) could or should change. Yet the types of systematic biases in the formulation and manipulation of subjective probabilities presented in the preceding section ("Other Issues: Is Probability Theory Relevant?") should cause the analyst to be especially careful in obtaining mutually consistent estimates of the underlying event likelihoods used in constructing the probability distributions over consequences implied by each option in step 2. Note that this step has nothing to do with the client's attitudes toward bearing these risks (i.e., whether or not they do, or should, maximize expected utility). Rather, it consists of applying probability theory to establish the internal consistency and (once that has been established) the logical implications of the client's or experts' probabilistic beliefs. If the client assigns probability .3 to the occurrence of some event A, probability .2 to the occurrence of some mutually exclusive event B, and probability .6 to the occurrence of neither, then at least one of these numbers will have to change before the pieces will fit. This situation is no different from that of asking a client for the length, width, and area of his or her living room before offering advice on a choice of carpet: if the numbers do not multiply out correctly then something is wrong, and the advising process should stop short until corrections are made. Although I suspect practitioners in the field have been aware of such inconsistencies (and of how to "iron them out") for some time now, the type of systematic and specific biases that psychologists have been uncovering now give decision analysts the opportunity, and, I feel, much more of an obligation, to search explicitly for and eliminate biases and inconsistencies in clients' probabilistic beliefs which might otherwise remain hidden.
Although I feel the suggestions of the previous paragraph are important, they are more of a technical improvement than a basic change in how step 2 is carried out. On the other hand, I would argue that the developments reviewed in this paper do imply a fundamental change in the way modern decision analysts should proceed with steps 3 and 4 (explicating clients' risk preferences and determining their optimal action). The classical approach would be essentially to impose the property of linearity in the probabilities on the client by assessing his or her yon Neumann-Morgenstern utility function and then using it to calculate the "optimal" (i.e., expected utility-maximizing) choice. If clients made choices like those in the Allais paradox, the common consequence effect, or the common ratio effect discussed earlier, or their responses to alternative assessment methods yielded different "recovered" utility functions, they would often be told that they had "inconsistent" (i.e., not expected utility) preferences that would have to be corrected before their optimal action could be determined.
Although experimental subjects and real-world decision makers sometimes do make mistakes in expressing their preferences, I feel that the widespread and systematic nature of "fanning out"-type departures from expected utility, and the growing number of models that can simultaneously accommodate this phenomenon, as well as the more traditional properties of stochastic dominance preference and risk aversion, increase both the analyst's ability and obligation to fit and represent clients' risk attitudes within a consistent non-expected utility framework when their expressed risk preferences are pointing in that direction.64 Why do I feel that departures from the strictures of probability theory should be corrected but that (systematic) departures from the strictures of expected utility theory should not? Because the former involve the determination of the risks involved in an option, which is a matter of accurate representation, whereas the latter involve the client's willingness to bear these risks, which is a matter of preference. To continue my earlier analogy, reporting a length, width, and area of a room that are not commensurate implies an internally inconsistent description of the room and is simply wrong; preferring purple polka-dot carpeting, however, is a matter of clients' tastes, to which they have every right if it is their living room. In the case of health or environmental risks, this would correspond to the distinction between measuring the detrimental effects of a drug or a pollutant versus determining the individual patient's or society's attitudes toward bearing these consequences.
Does this increased respect for clients' preferences mean that the decision analyst should not play any guiding role in steps 3 or 4? The answer is no: conscientious decision analysts will still try to elicit and explicitly represent the client's risk attitudes, their underlying properties (e.g., whether they are risk averse, linear in the probabilities, etc.), and their logical implications. Even more important, they will continue explicitly to separate their client's beliefs from their preferences. For example, let us say that, although option I offers a very high chance of an acceptable but not terrific outcome (e.g., amputation of a gangrenous limb), the client insists on "optimism" or "wishful thinking" in connection with option 2 (e.g., drug therapy), which is not as likely to succeed but does offer a small chance of obtaining the best possible outcome. In that case the decision analysis should take pains formally to represent the client's attitude as a willingness to bear risk (either by a convex utility function, such as as in Figure 1b, or by some non-expected utility counterpart) rather than as an exaggerated probability estimate of obtaining the best outcome under option 2. The job of the decision analyst has hardly become obsolete.
Implications for Public Decision Making
Although private-sector decision analysts typically act on behalf of an individual client or firm, the decision maker in federal, state, or local government is faced with the obligation of acting on the behalf of citizens whose preferences and interests will generally differ from one another. In the case of decisions under certainty, economists have developed a large body of techniques, collectively termed welfare economics or welfare analysis, with which to analyze such situations.65 Not surprisingly, economic theorists have also used the expected utility model as a framework for extending such analyses to a world of uncertainty (e.g., Arrow, 1953/1964, 1974; Diamond, 1967). Let us say, however, that we wish to respect what the recent evidence implies about individuals' actual attitudes toward risk. Can classical welfare analysis, the economist's most important tool for formal policy evaluation, be undertaken with these newer models of preferences?
The answer to this question depends on the model. Fanning-out behavior and the non-expected utility models used to characterize it, as well as the state-payoff approach discussed earlier, are completely consistent with the assumption of well-defined, transitive individual preference orderings and hence with traditional welfare analysis along the lines of Pareto (1909), Bergson (1938) and Samuelson (1947/1983:Chap. 8). For example, the proof of the general efficiency ("Pareto efficiency") of a system of complete contingent-commodity markets (Arrow, 1953/1964; Debreu, 1959:Chap. 7) requires neither the expected utility hypothesis nor the assumption of well-defined probabilistic beliefs. On the other hand, it is clear that the preference reversal phenomenon and framing effects, and at least some of the nontransitive or noneconomic models used to address them, will prove much more difficult to reconcile with welfare analysis, or at least with welfare analysis as currently practiced.
To see how some of these (transitive) non-expected utility models can be applied to policy questions, the reader may recall the earlier expected utility-based analysis of the trade-off between the probability p and magnitude L of a disastrous event (see the section entitled "The Expected Utility Model"). Under the expected utility hypothesis, it was seen that an individual's marginal rate of substitution (i.e., acceptable rate of trade-off) between these variables would vary exactly proportionally to the loss probability p (as seen in footnote 11). Although it requires a bit of algebra to do so, it is possible to demonstrate that if preferences depart from expected utility by "fanning out" (Figures 4b, 5a, 5b, and 6), then individuals' marginal rates of substitution between p and L will always vary less than proportionally to the loss probability p (Machina, 1983b:282-289). Although this is not as strong a prediction as expected utility theory's prediction of exact proportionality, it can be used to place at least a one-sided bound on how individuals' acceptable rates of trade-off behave. In any event, it is at least more closely tied to what has actually been observed about preferences over risky prospects.66
Public and Corporate Obligations in the Presentation of Information
The final issue concerns the public policy implications of framing effects. If individuals' choices actually depend on the manner in which publicly or privately supplied probabilistic information (e.g., cancer incidences or flood probabilities) is presented, then the manner of presentation itself becomes a public policy issue over which interest groups may well contend. Should "freedom of information" imply that a government or manufacturer has an obligation to present a broad range of "legitimate" frames when disclosing required information, or would this practice lead to confusion and waste? Should legal rights of recourse for failures to provide information (e.g., job or product hazards) extend to failures to frame it "properly"? The general issue of public perception of risk is of growing concern to a number of government agencies—in particular, the Environmental Protection Agency.67 To the extent that new products, medical techniques, and environmental hazards continue to appear and the government takes a role their regulation, these issues will become more and more pressing.
Although the issue of the public and private framing of probabilistic information is a comparatively new one, I feel that there are several analogous issues (not all of them fully resolved) from which useful insights may be derived. Previous examples have included the cash discount/credit surcharge issue mentioned earlier, rotating warning labels on cigarette packages, financial disclosure regulations, bans on certain forms of alcohol advertising, publicity requirements for product recall announcements, and current debate cover such issues as requiring special labels on irradiated produce or on products imported from countries that engage in human or animal rights violations, or both. If these issues do not provide ready-made answers for the case of probabilistic information, they at least allow a glimpse of how policy makers, interest groups, and the public feel and act toward the general issue of the presentation of information.
Acknowledgment
This paper is an adapted and expanded version of Machina (1987). I am grateful to Brian Binger, John Conlisk, Rob Coppock, Jim Cox, Vince Crawford, Gong Jin-Dong, Elizabeth Hoffman, Brett Hammond, Paul Portney, Howard Raiffa, Michael Rothschild, Carl Shapiro, Vernon Smith, Joseph Stiglitz, Timothy Taylor, Richard Thaler, and especially Joel Sobel for helpful discussions on this material.
Editors' Note
In the preceding paper, Mark Machina addresses an important set of questions relevant to the use of benefit-cost analysis in regulatory decision making. These include:
- How do (and should) decision makers and analysts cope with uncertainties in the science underlying decisions?
- How does the way in which information is presented—or framed—affect analysis and regulatory decisions?
- Is it possible to get better estimates of uncertainty for purposes of practical decision making?
Machina examines recent theoretical and empirical findings on how people actually evaluate risks and assign probabilities in arriving at policy preferences. Much of this literature challenges the traditional economic approach to preferences, in that it points out that individuals are able to sustain nonlinearity in their subjective assessments of probabilities, reversal of preferences over time or between different situations, and differences in preferences and probability assessments depending on the way in which a problem (or analysis) is framed or presented.
At the heart of his paper is the conclusion that predicted policy outcomes should be differentiated from individual and collective policy preferences for purposes of analysis and decision making. As he puts it, observed ''departures from the strictures of probability theory should be corrected [by the analyst or the decision maker] but that [systematic] departures from the structures of expected utility theory should not." This is because the former involved the determination of the risks associated with alternative actions or policies, which are in fact matters of accurate representation, while the latter involve the willingness of individuals, organizations, and society to bear these risks, which is a matter of preference.
He concludes that analysis must be designed to account for actual preferences, even those that depart from the tenets of expected utility theory. Therefore, analysts and decision makers, in assigning values to policy alternatives, may need to consider departures from expected utility and weighting schemes to reflect those departures.
References
- Akerlof, G. 1970. The market for "Lemons": Quality uncertainty and the market mechanism. Quarterly Journal of Economics 84:488-500.
- 1984. An Economic Theorist's Book of Tales. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Allais, M. 1952. Fondements d'une théorie positive des choix comportant un risque et critique des postulats et axiomes de l'ecole Américaine. Econométrie , Colloques Internationaux du Centre National de h Recherche Scientific 40: Paris, 1953, 257-332.
- 1953. Le comportement de l'homme rationel derant le risque, Critique des postulates et axiomes de l'ecole Américaine. Econometrica 21:503-546. Summarized version of Allais (1952).
- 1979. a The foundations of a positive theory of choice involving risk and a criticism of the postulates and axioms of the American school. Pp. 27-145 in M. Allais, editor; and O. Hagen, editor. , eds. Expected Utility Hypotheses and the Allais Pardox. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
- 1979. b The so-called Allais paradox and rational decisions under uncertainty. Pp. 437-681 in M. Allais, editor; and O. Hagen, editor. , eds. Expected Utility Hypotheses and the Allais Pardox. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
- Allen, B. 1987. Smooth preferences and the local expected utility hypothesis. Journal of Economic Theory 41:340-355.
- Arrow, K. 1951. Alternative approaches to the theory of choice in risk-taking situations. Econometrica 19:404-437.
- 1953. Le role des valeurs boursières pour la répartition le meilleure des risques. Econométrie, Colloques Internationaux du Centre National de la Recherche Scientific 40, Paris, 1953, 41-47.
- 1963. Comment. Review of Economics and Statistics 45(Suppl.):24-27.
- 1964. The role of securities in the optimal allocation of risk-bearing. Review of Economic Studies 31:91-96.
- 1974. Essays in the Theory of Risk-Bearing. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.
- 1982. Risk perception in psychology and economics. Economic Inquiry 20:1-9.
- Arrow, K., and L. Hurwicz 1972. An optimality criterion for decision making under ignorance. Pp. 1-11 in Carter, D., editor; , and E. Ford, editor. , eds., Uncertainty and Expectations in Economics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
- Arrow, K., editor; , and M. Intriligator, editor. , eds. 1981. Handbook of Mathematical Economics , vol. 1. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.
- Bar-Hillel, M. 1973. On the subjective probability of compound events. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance 9:396-406.
- 1974. Similarity and probability. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance 11:277-282.
- Battalio, R., J. Kagel, and D. MacDonald 1985. Animals' choices over uncertain outcomes. American Economic Review 75:597-613.
- Becker, G., M. DeGroot, and J. Marschak 1964. Measuring utility by a single-response sequential method. Behavioral Science 9:226-232. [PubMed: 5888778]
- Becker, S., and E. Brownson 1964. What price ambiguity? Or the role of ambiguity in decision making. Journal of Political Economy 72:62-73.
- Bell, D. 1982. Regret in decision making under uncertainty. Operations Research 30:961-980.
- 1983. Risk premiums for decision regret. Management Science 29:1066-1076.
- 1985. Disappointment in decision making under uncertainty. Operations Research 33:1-27.
- Bell, D., and H. Raiffa 1980. Decision Regret: A Component of Risk Aversion. Unpublished manuscript, Harvard University.
- Berg, J., J. Dickhaut, and J. O'Brien 1983. Preference Reversal and Arbitrage. Unpublished manuscript, University of Minnesota.
- Bergson, A. 1938. A reformulation of certain aspects of welfare economics. Quarterly Journal of Economics 52:310-334.
- Bernoulli, D. 1738. Specimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis. Commentarii Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae [Papers of the Imperial Academy of Sciences in Petersburg] 5:175-192. English translation: Exposition of a new theory on the measurement of risk. Econometrica 22(1954):23-36.
- Blyth, C. 1972. Some probability paradoxes in choice from among random alternatives. Journal of the Amman Statistical Association 67:366-373.
- Brewer, K. 1963. Decisions under uncertainty: Comment. Quarterly Journal of Economics 77:159-161.
- Brewer, K., and W. Fellner 1965. The slanting of subjective probabilities-Agreement on some essentials. Quarterly Journal of Economics 79:657-663.
- Chew, S. 1983. A generalization of the quasilinear mean with applications to the measurement of income inequality and decision theory resolving the Allais Paradox. Econometrica 51:1065-1092.
- Chew, S., and K. MacCrimmon 1979. a Alpha-Nu Choice Theory: A Generalization of Expected Utility Theory. University of British Columbia Faculty of Commerce and Business Administration Working Paper No. 669.
- 1979. b Alpha Utility Theory, Lottery Composition, and the Allah Paradox. University of British Columbia Faculty of Commerce and Business Administration Working Paper No. 686.
- Chew, S., and W. Waller 1986. Empirical tests of weighted utility theory. Journal of Mathematical Psychology 30:55-72.
- Chew, S., E. Karni, and Z. Safra 1987. Risk aversion in the theory of expected utility with rank dependent probabilities. Journal of Economic Theory 42:370-381.
- Davis, J. 1958. The transitivity of preferences. Behavioral Science 3:26-33.
- Debreu, G. 1959. Theory of Value: An Axiomatic Analysis of General Equilibrium. New Haven: Yale University Press.
- Dekel, E. 1986. An axiomatic characterization of preferences under uncertainty: Weakening the independence axiom. Journal of Economic Theory 40:304-318.
- Diamond, P. 1967. The role of a stock market in a general equilibrium model with technological uncertainty. American Economic Review 57:759-773.
- Diamond, P., editor; , and M. Rothschild, editor. , eds. 1978. Uncertainty in Economics. New York: Academic Press.
- Diamond, P., and M. Yaari 1972. Implications of the theory of rationing for consumer choice under uncertainty. American Economic Review 62:333-343.
- Edwards, W. 1954. a Probability-preferences among bets with differing expected value. American Journal of Psychology 67:56-67. [PubMed: 13138769]
- 1955. The prediction of decisions among bets. Journal of Experimental Psychology 50:201-214. [PubMed: 13252198]
- 1962. Subjective probabilities inferred from decisions. Psychological Review 69:109-135. [PubMed: 13889319]
- 1971. Bayesian and regression models of human information processing-A myopic perspective. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance 6:639-648.
- Edwards, W., H. Lindman, and L. Savage 1963. Bayesian statistical inference for psychological research. Psychological Review 70:193-242.
- Einhorn, H., and R. Hogarth 1986. Decision making under ambiguity. Journal of Business 59(Suppl.):S225-S250.
- Ellsberg, D. 1961. Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics 75:643-669.
- 1963. Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms: Reply. Quarterly Journal of Economics 77:336-342.
- Epstein, L. 1985. Decreasing risk aversion and mean-variance analysis. Econometrica 53:945-961.
- 1987. The unimportance of the intransitivity of separable preference. International Economic Review 28:315-322.
- Feather, N. 1959. Subjective probability and decision under uncertainty. Psychological Review 66:150-164. [PubMed: 13658302]
- Fellner, W. 1961. Distortion of subjective probabilities as a reaction to uncertainty. Quarterly Journal of Economics 75:670-489.
- 1963. Slanted subjective probabilities and randomization: Reply to Howard Raiffa and K. R. W. Brewer. Quarterly Journal of Economics 77:676-690.
- Fischhoff, B. 1983. Predicting frames. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning. Memory and Cognition 9:103-116.
- Fishburn, P. 1981. An axiomatic characterization of skew-symmetric bilinear functionals, with applications to utility theory. Economics Letters 8:311-313.
- 1982. Nontransitive measurable utility. Journal of Mathematical Psychology 26:31-67.
- 1982. Transitive measurable utility. Journal of Economic Theory 31:293-317.
- 1984. a SSB utility theory: An economic perspective. Mathematical Social Sciences 8:63-94.
- 1994. b SSB utility theory and decision making under uncertainty. Mathematical Social Sciences 8:253-285.
- 1966. A new model for decisions under uncertainty. Economics Letters 21:127-130.
- 1988. Uncertainty aversion and separated effects in decision making under uncertainty. In J. Kacprzyk, editor; and M. Fedrizzi, editor. , eds., Combining Fuzzy Impressions With Probabilistic Uncertainty in Decision Making. Berlin: Springer Verlag.
- Fishburn, P., and G. Kochenberger 1979. Two-piece Von Neumann-Morgenstern utility functions. Decision Sciences 10:503-518.
- Friedman, M., and L. Savage 1948. The utility analysis of choices involving risk. Journal of Political Economy 56:279-304. Reprinted with revisions in Stigler and Boulding (1952).
- Grether, D. 1978. Recent psychological studies of behavior under uncertainty. American Economic Review Papers and Proceedings 68:70-74.
- 1980. Bayes rule as a descriptive model: The representativeness heuristic. Quarterly Journal of Economics 95:537-557.
- Grether, D., and C. Plott 1979. Economic theory of choice and the preference reversal phenomenon. American Economic Review 69:623-638.
- Grofman, B., editor; , and G. Owen, editor. , eds. 1986. Information Pooling and Group Decision Making. Greenwich, Conn.: JAI Press.
- Hagen, O. 1979. Towards a positive theory of preferences under risk. Pp. 271-302 in M. Allais, editor; and O. Hagen, editor. , eds. Expected Utility Hypotheses and the Allais Paradox Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
- Henderson, J., and R. Quandt 1980. Microeconomic Theory: A Mathematical Approach, 3d ed. New York: McGraw-Hill.
- Hershey, J., and P. Schoemaker 1980. a Prospect theory's reflection hypothesis: A critical examination. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance 25:395-418.
- 1980. b Risk-taking and problem context in the domain of losses—An expected utility analysis. Journal of Risk and Insurance 47:111-132.
- 1985. Probability versus certainty equivalence methods in utility measurement: Are they equivalent? Management Science 31:1213-1231.
- Hershey, J., H. Kunreuther, and P. Schoemaker 1982. Sources of bias in assessment procedures for utility functions. Management Science 28:936-954.
- Hey, J. 1979. Uncertainty in Microeconomics. Oxford: Martin Robinson and Company, Ltd.
- Hirshleifer, J. 1965. Investment decision under uncertainty: Choice-theoretic approaches. Quarterly Journal of Economics 79:509-536.
- 1966. Investment decision under uncertainty: Applications of the state-preference approach. Quarterly Journal of Economics 80:252-277.
- Hogarth, R. 1975. Cognitive processes and the assessment of subjective probability distributions. Journal of the American Statistical Association 70:271-289.
- 1980. Judgment and Choice: The Psychology of Decision. New York: John Wiley and Sons.
- Hogarth, R., and H. Kunreuther 1986. Risk, Ambiguity and Insurance. Unpublished manuscript, University of Chicago.
- 1989. Risk, ambiguity and insurance. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 2:5-35.
- Hogarth, R., editor; , and M. Reder, editor. , eds. 1987. Rational Choice: The Contrast Between Economics and Psychology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
- Holt, C. 1986. Preference reversals and the independence axiom. American Economic Review 76:508-515.
- Kahneman, D., and A. Tversky 1973. On the psychology of prediction., Psychological Review 80:237-251.
- 1979. Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica 47:263-291.
- 1982. The psychology of preferences. Scientific American 246:160-173.
- 1984. Choices, values and frames. American Psychologist 39:341-350.
- Kahneman, D., editor; , P. Slovic, editor; , and A. Tversky, editor. , eds. 1982. Judgment Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Karmarkar, U. 1974. The Effect of Probabilities on the Subjective Evaluation of Lotteries. Massachusetts Institute of Technology Sloan School of Business Working Paper No. 698-74.
- 1978. Subjectively weighted utility: A descriptive extension of the expected utility model. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance 21:61-72.
- 1979. Subjectively weighted utility and the Allais paradox. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance 24:67-72.
- Karni, E. 1985. Decision Making Under Uncertainty: The Case of State Dependent Preferences. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
- Karni, E., and Z. Safra 1987. "Preference reversal" and the observability of preferences by experimental methods. Econometrica 55:675-685.
- Keeney, R., and H. Raiffa 1976. Decisions with Multiple Objectives: Preferences and Value Tradeoffs. New York: John Wiley and Sons.
- Keller, L. 1985. The effects of decision problem representation on utility conformance. Management Science 6:738-751.
- Kihlstrom, R., D. Romer, and S. Williams 1981. Risk aversion with random initial wealth. Econometrica 49:911-920.
- Kim, T., and M. Richter 1986. Nontransitive-nontotal consumer theory. Journal of Economic Theory 38:324-363.
- Knetsch, J., and J. Sinden 1984. Willingness to pay and compensation demanded: Experimental evidence of an unexpected disparity in measures of value. Quarterly Journal of Economics 99:507-521.
- Knez, M., and V. Smith 1987. Hypothetical valuations and preference reversals in the context of asset trading. Pp. 131-154 in A. Roth, editor. , ed., Laboratory Experiments in Economics: Six Points of View. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Lichtenstein, S., and P. Slovic 1971. Reversals of preferences between bids and choices in gambling decisions. Journal of Experimental Psychology 89:46-55.
- 1973. Response-induced reversals of preference in gambling: An extended replication in Las Vegas. Journal of Experimental Psychology 101:16-20.
- Lindman, H. 1971. Inconsistent preferences among gambles. Journal of Experimental Psychology 89:390-397.
- Lippman, S., and J. McCall 1981. The economics of uncertainty: Selected topics and probabilistic methods. Pp. 211-284 in K Arrow, editor; and M. Intriligator, editor. , eds., Handbook of Mathematical Economics, vol. 1. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.
- Loomes, G., and R. Sugden 1982. Regret theory: An alternative theory of rational choice under uncertainty. Economic Journal 92:805-824.
- 1983. a Regret theory and measurable utility. Economics Letters 12:19-22.
- 1983. b A rationale for preference reversal. American Economic Review 73:428-432.
- MacCrimmon, K. 1965. An Experimental Study of the Decision Making Behavior of Business Executives. Doctoral dissertation, University of California, Los Angeles.
- 1968. Descriptive and normative implications of the derision-theory postulates. Pp. 3-23 in K. Borch, editor; and J. Mossin, editor. , Risk and Uncertainty: Proceedings of a Conference Held by the International Economic Association. London: Macmillan and Company.
- MacCrimmon, K., and S. Larsson 1979. Utility theory: Axioms versus "Paradoxes." Pp. 333-409 in M. Allais, editor; and O. Hagen, editor. , eds., Expected Utility Hypotheses and the Allais Paradox. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
- MacCrimmon, K., and D. Wehrung 1986. Taking Risks: The Management of Uncertainty. New York: The Free Press.
- Machina, M. 1982. "Expected utility" analysis without the independence axiom. Econometrica 50:277-323.
- 1983. a The Economic Theory of Individual Behavior Toward Risk: Theory, Evidence and New Directions. Stanford University Institute for Mathematical Studies in the Social Sciences Technical Report No. 443.
- 1983. b Generalized expected utility analysis and the nature of observed violations of the independence axiom. Pp. 263-293 in B. Stigum, editor; and E. Wenstop, editor. , Foundations of Utility and Risk Theory with Applications. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
- 1984. Temporal risk and the nature of induced preferences. Journal of Economic Theory 33:199-231.
- 1987. Choice under uncertainty: Problems solved and unsolved. Journal of Economic Perspectives 1:121-154.
- Machina, M., and W. Neilson 1987. The Ross measure of risk aversion: Strengthening and extension. Econometrica 55:1139-1149.
- Markowitz, H. 1952. The utility of wealth. Journal of Political Economy 60:151-158.
- 1959. Portfolio Selection: Efficient Diversification of Investments. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press.
- Marschak, J. 1950. Rational behavior, uncertain prospects, and measurable utility. Econometrica 18:111-141 (Errata. Econometrica 18: 312).
- 1974. Economic Information, Decision, and Prediction, 3 vols. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
- Mas-Colell, A. 1974. An equilibrium existence theorem without complete or transitive preferences. Journal of Mathematical Economies 3:237-246.
- Maskin, E. 1979. Decision making under ignorance with implications for social choice. Theory and Decision 11:319-337.
- May, K. 1954. Intransitivity, utility, and the aggregation of preference patterns. Econometrica 22:1-13.
- McCord, M., and R. de Neufville 1983. Empirical demonstration that expected utility analysis is not operational. Pp. 181-199 in B. Stigum, editor; and E. Wenstøp, editor. , Foundations of Utility and Risk Theory with Applications. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
- McCord, M., and R. de Neufville 1984. Utility dependence on probability: An empirical demonstration. Large Scale Systems 6:91-103.
- McNeil, B., S. Pauker, H. Sox, and A. Tversky 1982. On the elicitation of preferences for alternative therapies. New England Journal of Medicine 306:1259-1262. [PubMed: 7070445]
- Milne, E. 1981. Induced preferences and the theory of the consumer. Journal of Economic Theory 24:205-217.
- Mishan, E. 1976. Choices involving risk: Simple steps toward an ordinalist analysis. Economic Journal 86:759-777.
- Morrison, D. 1967. On the consistency of preferences in Allais' paradox. Behavioral Science 12:373-383. [PubMed: 6059769]
- Moskowitz, H. 1974. Effects of problem representation and feedback on rational behavior in Allais and Morlat-type problems. Decision Sciences 5:225-242.
- Mowen, J., and J. Gentry 1980. Investigation of the preference-reversal phenomenon in a new product introduction task. Journal of Applied Psychology 65:715-722.
- Pareto, V. 1909. Manuel d'Economie Politique. Paris: V. Girard et E. Brière.
- Parkin, M., editor; , and A. Nobay, editor. , eds. 1975. Current Economic Problems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Payne, J., and M. Braunstein 1971. Preferences among gambles with equal underlying distributions. Journal of Experimental Psychology 87:13-18.
- Payne, J., D. Laughhunn, and R. Crum 1980. Translation of gambles and aspiration level effects in risky choice behavior. Management Science 26:1039-1060.
- 1981. Further tests of aspiration level effects in risky choice behavior. Management Science 27:953-958.
- Pommerehne, W., E. Schneider, and P. Zweifel 1982. Economic theory of choice and the preference reversal phenomenon: A reexamination. American Economic Review 72:569-574.
- Pratt, J. 1964. Risk aversion in the small and in the large. Econometrica 32:122-136.
- Quiggin, J. 1982. A theory of anticipated utility. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 3:323-343.
- Raiffa, H. 1961. Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics 75:690-694.
- 1968. Decision Analysis: Introductory Lectures on Choice Under Uncertainty. Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley.
- Reilly, R. 1982. Preference reversal: Further evidence and some suggested modifications of experimental design. American Economic Review 72:576-584.
- Roberts, H. 1963. Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms: Comment. Quarterly Journal of Economics 77:327-336.
- Röell, A. 1987. Risk aversion in Quiggin and Yaari's rank-order model of choice under uncertainty. Economic Journal 97(Suppl.):143-159.
- Ross, S. 1981. Some stronger measures of risk aversion in the small and in the large with applications. Econometrica 49:621-638.
- Rothschild, M., and J. Stiglitz 1970. Increasing risk: I. A definition. Journal of Economic Theory 2:225-243.
- 1971. Increasing risk: II. Its economic consequences. Journal of Economic Theory 3:66-84.
- Russo, J. 1977. The value of unit price information. Journal of Marketing Research 14:193-201.
- Russo, J. G. Krieser, and S. Miyashita 1975. An effective display of unit price information. Journal of Marketing 39:11-19.
- Samuelson, P. 1947. Foundations of Economic Analysis. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Enlarged edition, 1983.
- 1952. Probability, utility, and the independence axiom. Econometrica 20:670-678.
- 1977. St. Petersburg paradoxes: Deranged, dissected, and historically described. Journal of Economic Literature 15:24-55.
- Savage, L. 1954. The Foundations of Statistics. New York: John Wiley and Sons. Revised and enlarged edition published by Dover Publications (New York, 1972).
- Schlaifer, R. 1969. Analysis of Decisions Under Uncertainty. New York: McGraw-Hill Publishing Co..
- Schmeidler, D. 1989. Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. Econometrica 57:571-587.
- Schoemaker, P. 1980. Experiments on Decisions Under Risk: The Expected Utility Hypothesis. Boston: Martinus Nijhoff Publishing.
- Schoemaker, P., and H. Kunreuther 1979. An experimental study of insurance decisions. Journal of Risk and Insurance 46:603-618.
- Segal, U. 1984. Nonlinear Decision Weights with the Independence Axiom. Unpublished manuscript, University of California, Los Angeles.
- 1987. The Ellsberg paradox and risk aversion: An anticipated utility approach. International Economic Review 28:175-202.
- Shafer. W. 1974. The nontransitive consumer. Econometrica 42:913-919.
- 1976. Equilibrium in economies without ordered preferences or free disposal. Journal of Mathematical Economics 3:135-137.
- Sherman, R. 1974. The psychological difference between ambiguity and risk. Quarterly Journal of Economics 88:166-169.
- Sinn, H.-W. 1980. A rehabilitation of the principle of sufficient reason. Quarterly Journal of Economics 94:493-506.
- Slovic, P. 1969. a Differential effects of real versus hypothetical payoffs on choices among gambles. Journal of Experimental Psychology 80:434-437.
- 1969. b Manipulating the attractiveness of a gamble without changing its expected value. Journal of Experimental Psychology 79:139-145.
- 1975. Choice between equally valued alternatives. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 1:280-287.
- Slovic, P., and S. Lichtenstein 1968. Relative important of probabilities and payoffs in risk taking. Journal of Psychology 78(3, Part 2):1-18.
- Slovic, P., and S. Lichtenstein 1971. Comparison of Bayesian and regression approaches to the study of information processing in judgment. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance 6:649-744.
- Slovic, P., and S. Lichtenstein 1983. Preference reversals: A broader perspective. American Economic Review 73:596-605.
- Slovic P., and A. Tversky 1974. Who accepts Savage's axiom? Behavioral Science 19:368-373.
- Slovic, P., B. Fischhoff, and S. Lichtenstein 1982. Response mode, framing, and information processing effects in risk assessment. Pp. 21-36 in R. Hogarth, editor. , ed., New Directions for Methodology of Social and Behavioral Science: Question Framing and Response Consistency. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
- Smith, V. 1969. Measuring nonmonetary utilities in uncertain choices: The Ellsberg urn. Quarterly Journal of Economics 88:324-329.
- Sonnenschein, H. 1971. Demand theory without transitive preferences, with applications to the theory of competitive equilibrium. Pp. 215-233 in J. Chipman, editor; , L. Hurwicz, editor; , M. Richter, editor; , and H. Sonnenschein, editor. , eds., Preferences, Utility, and Demand. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, Inc.
- Spence, M., and R. Zeckhauser 1971. Insurance, information, and individual action. American Economic Review 61:380-387.
- Stigler, G., editor; , and K. Boulding, editor. , eds. 1952. Readings in Price Theory. Chicago: Richard D. Irwin.
- Stiglitz, J. 1975. Information and economic analysis. Pp. 27-52 in M. Parkin, editor; and A. Nobay, editor. , eds., Current Economic Problems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- 1985. Information and economic analysis: A perspective. Economic Journal 95(Suppl.): 21-41.
- Stiglitz, J., editor. , ed. 1966. Collected Scientific Papers of Paul A. Samuelson, vol. 1. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
- Sugden, R. 1966. New developments in the theory of choice under uncertainty. Bulletin of Economic Research 38:1-24.
- Thaler, R. 1980. Toward a positive theory of consumer choice. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 1:39-60.
- 1985. Mental accounting and consumer choice. Marketing Science 4:199-214.
- Tversky, A. 1969. Intransitivity of preferences. Psychological Review 76:31-48.
- 1975. A critique of expected utility theory: Descriptive and normative considerations. Erkenntnis 9:163-173.
- Tversky, A., and D. Kahneman 1971. Belief in the law of small numbers. Psychological Bulletin 2:105-110.
- 1983. Extensional vs. intuitive reasoning: The conjunction fallacy in probability judgment. Psychological Review 90:293-315. [PMC free article: PMC4658440] [PubMed: 26635712]
- Viscusi, W. 1985. a Are individuals Bayesian decision makers? American Economic Review Papers and Proceedings 75:381-385.
- 1985. b A Bayesian perspective on biases in risk perception. Economics Letters 17:59-62.
- von Neumann, J., and O. Morgenstern 1947. Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, 2d ed., editor. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
- Weber, M., editor; , and C. Camerer, editor. 1987. Recent developments in modeling preferences under risk. OR Spektrum 9:129-151.
- Weinstein, A. 1968. Individual preference intransitivity. Southern Economic Journal 34:335-343.
- Williams, C. 1966. Attitudes toward speculative risks as an indicator of attitudes toward pure risks. Journal of Risk and Insurance 33:577-586.
- Yaari, M. 1969. Some remarks on measures of risk aversion and on their uses. Journal of Economic Theory 1:315-329.
- 1987. The dual theory of choice under risk. Econometrica 55:95-115.
Footnotes
- 1
See, for example, von Neumann and Morgenstern (1947), Marschak (1950), and Savage (1954).
- 2
See, for example, Arrow (1963, 1974), Pratt (1964) and Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970, 1971). For surveys of applications, see Lippman and McCall (1981) and Hey (1979).
- 3
See, for example, Akerlof (1970) and Spence and Zeckhauser (1971). For overviews of the subsequent development of this area, see Stiglitz (1975, 1985).
- 4
Bernoulli (1738). For a historical overview of the St. Petersburg paradox and its impact, see Samuelson (1977).
- 5
Algebraically, the certainty equivalent of the Petersburg gamble is given by the value ξ that solves U(W + ξ) = (1/2)U(W + 1) + (1/4) U(W +2) + (1/8)U(W +4) + ..., where W denotes the individual's initial wealth (i.e., wealth going into the gamble).
- 6
Thus, for example, a 2/3:1/3 chance of $100 or $20 and a 1/2:1/2 chance of $100 or $30 both stochastically dominate a 1/2:1/2 chance of $100 or $20.
- 7
How risk attitudes actually differ over gains versus losses is itself an unsolved problem: evidence consistent with or contradictory to the Friedman-Savage observation of risk seeking over gains and risk aversion over losses can be found in Williams (1966), Kahneman and Tversky (1979), Fish burn and Kochen berger (1979), Grether and Plott (1979), Hershey and Schoemaker (1980a), Payne, Laughhunn, and Crum (1980, 1981), Hershey, Kunreuther, and Schoemaker (1952), and the references cited in these articles. Finally, Feather (1959) and Slovic (1969a) found evidence that subjects' risk attitudes over gains and losses systematically changed when hypothetical situations were replaced by situations involving real money.
- 8
For example, if Uc(·) and Ud(·) satisfy - for all x [i.e., if Uc(·) is at least as risk averse as Ud, (·)], an individual with utility function Uc (·) would always be willing to pay at least as much as an individual with utility function Ud (·) for (complete) insurance against any risk. See also the related analyses of Ross (1981) and Kihlstrom, Romer, and Williams (1981).
- 9
Because the utility of ix will equal the expected utility of the gamble, it follows that U(ξ1 = (1/2)U(M) + (1/2)U(0), which under the normalization U(0) = 0 and U(M) = 1 will equal 1/2.
- 10
As in the previous note, U(ξ2) = (1/2)U(ξ1) + (1/2)U(0) and U(ξ3) = (1/2)U(M) + (1/2)U(ξ1), which from the normalization U(0) = 0, U(M) = 1 and the fact that U(ξ1) = 1/2 will equal 1/4 and 3/4, respectively.
- 11
Because expected utility in this example is given by (where W is initial wealth or lives), an application of the standard economic formula for the marginal rate of substitution (e.g., see Henderson and Quandt [1980:10-11])yields which, for fixed L, varies proportionately with p.
- 12
Thus, if x1 = $20, x2 = $30, and x3 = $100, the three prospects in footnote 6 would be represented by the points (p1, p3) = (1/3, 2/3), (p1, p3) = (0, 1/2) and (p1, p3) = (1/2, 1/2), respectively.
- 13
Although it is fair to describe the renewal of interest in this approach as "modern," modified versions of this triangle diagram can be found as far back as Marschak (1950) and Markowitz (1959: Chap 11).
- 14
A useful analogy to the concept of indifference curves is the "constant-altitude" curves on a topographic map, each of which connect points of the same altitude. Just as these curves can be used to determine whether a given movement on the map will lead to a greater or lower altitude, indifference curves can be used to determine whether a given movement in the triangle will lead to greater or lower expected utility.
- 15
See, for example, Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970, 1971).
- 16
This follows because the slope of the indifference curves can be calculated to be [U(x2)-U(x1)]/[U(x3) - U(x2)], the dope of the iso-expected value lines can be calculated to be [x2 -x1]/[x3 - x2], and a concave shape for U(·) implies [U(x2) - U(x1)]/[x2-x1] > [U( x3) -U(x2)]/[x3 - x2] whenever x1 < x2 < x3.
- 17
Setting his v, w, x, and y equal to x1, x2, x2, and x3, respectively, this follows directly from theorem 1 of Pratt (1964).
- 18
See, for example, Marschak (1950) and Samuelson (1952).
- 19
See, for example, Allais (1952, 1953, 1979a).
- 20
Algebraically, these two cases are equivalent to the expression [.10.U(5,000,000) - .11· U(1,000,000) + .01.U(0)], being respectively negative or positive.
- 21
Let P be a gain of $1 million, let P* be a (10/11):(1/11) chance of $5 million or $0, and let α = .11. The choice between a1 and a2 is then equivalent to a choice between αP + (1 - α)P** and αP* + (1 - α)P** when P** is a gain of $1 million; the choice between a4 and a3 is a choice between αP + (1 - α)P** and αP* + (1 - α)P** when P** is a gain of $0. Thus one should choose a1 and a4 if P is preferred to P* or a2 and a3 if P* is preferred to P.
- 22
Reports of this incident can be found in Savage (1954:101-103) and Allais (1979b:533-535). In that instance the payoffs of {$0;$1 million;$5 million) in the displayed example were replaced by {$0;$500,000;$2.5 million) (1952 dollars).
- 23
In each of MacCrimmon's experiments, for example, he obtained approximately 60 percent conformity with the independence axiom (1968:7-11). However, when presented with opposing written arguments, the pro-expected utility argument was chosen by only 20 percent of the subjects in the first experiment and 50 percent of the subjects in the second experiment (subjects in the third experiment were not presented with written arguments). In subsequent interviews with the experimenter, the percentage of subjects conforming to the independence axiom did rise to 75 percent. Although MacCrimmon did not apply pressure to induce the subjects to adopt expected utility and "repeatedly emphasized that there was no fight or wrong answer," he personally believed in "the desirability of using the [expected utility] postulates in training decision makers" (1968:21-22), a fact that Slovic and Tversky felt "may have influenced the subjects to conform to the axioms" (1974:369).
- 24
The Allah Paradox choices a1, a2, a3, and a4 correspond to b1, b2, b4, and b3, where a = .11, x = $1 million, P is a (10/11):(1/11) chance of $5 million or $0, P* = is a sure gain of $0, and P** is a sure gain of $1 million.
- 25
See MacCrimmon (1968), MacCrimmon and Larsson (1979), Kahneman and Tversky (1979) and Chew and Waller (1986).
- 26
As Bell (1985) notes, "winning the top prize of $10,000 in a lottery may leave one much happier than receiving $10,000 as the lowest prize in a lottery."
- 27
In a conversation with the author, Kenneth Arrow has offered an alternative phrasing of this argument: The widely maintained hypothesis of decreasing absolute risk aversion asserts that individuals will display more risk aversion in the event of a loss and less risk aversion in the event of a gain. In the common consequence effect, individuals display more risk aversion in the event of an opportunity loss, and less risk aversion in the event of an opportunity gain.
- 28
The former involves setting p = 1, and the latter consists of a two-step choice problem in which individuals exhibit the effect with Y = 2X and p = 2q. Kahneman and Tversky (1979), for example, found that 80 percent of their subjects preferred a sure gain of 3,000 Israeli pounds to a .80 chance of winning 4,000; 65 percent, however, preferred a .20 chance of winning 4,000 to a .25 chance of winning 3,000. The name "common ratio effect" comes from the common value of prob(X)/prob(Y) in the pairs { c1, c2 } and {c3, c4}.
- 29
See Tversky (1975), MacCrimmon and Larsson (1979), and Chew and Waller (1986).
- 30
Having found the value ξ1 that solves U'(ξ1) = (1/2)U (M) + (1/2) U(0), let us now choose {x1, x2, x3} = {0, ξ1, M}, so that the indifference curve through the point (0,0) (i.e., a sure gain of ξ1) also passes through the point (1/2, 1/2) (a 1/2:1/2 chance of M or 0). The ordering of the values ξ1, ξ2, ξ3, and in Figure 6a is derived from the individual's preference ordering over the five distributions in Figure 6b for which they are the respective certainty equivalents.
- 31
More complete developments of this approach my be found in Machina (1982, 1983b).
- 32
As in footnote 16, this is equivalent to the condition that [U( xi+1) - U(xi)]/[xi+1 - xi] < [U(xi) - U(xi-1)]/[xi - xi-1 for all i.
- 33
This is equivalent to the condition that for some increasing concave functionρ (·).
- 34
For the appropriate generalizations of the expected utility concepts of "at least as risk averse" in this result, see Machina (1982, 1984).
- 35
See, for example, Machina (1982, 1983b, 1984); Chew (1983); Fishburn (1984a); Epstein (1985); Dekel (1986); Allen (1987); Chew, Karni, and Safra (1987); Karni and Safra (1987), and Machina and Neilson (1987).
- 36
Roughly speaking, the subject states a value for the item and then the experimenter draws a random price. If the price is above the stated value, the subject forgoes the item and receives the price. If the drawn price is below the stated value, the subject keeps the item. The reader can verify that under such a scheme, it will never be in a subject's best interest to report anything other than his or her true value.
- 37
Economic theory tells us that income effects may well lead an individual to assign a lower bid price to the object that, if both were free, would actually be preferred. However, such an effect will not apply to either selling prices or the Becker, DeGroot, and Marschak procedure. For discussions of the empirical evidence on sell price/bid price disparities, see Knetsch and Sinden (1984) and the references cited there.
- 38
In addition to the problem with bid prices discussed in the previous note, Grether and Plott (1979) noted that subjects' changing wealth (as a result of the actual play of these gambles during the course of the experiment), or the changing of their expected wealth (in those experiments in which chosen gambles would be played at the end), could be a source of income effects.
- 39
Formally, this ordering is represented by the individual's weak preference relation, where "" is read "A is at least as preferred as B." From this one may in turn derive the individual's strict preference relation > and indifference relation ~, where "A>B" denotes that but not , and "A ~ B'' denotes that both and .
- 40
See also the discussions of these findings by Edwards (1954b:404-405), Davis (1958:28), and Weinstein (1968:337).
- 41
Algebraically, this expected value is given by the double summation .
- 42
This follows because , so that the individual will prefer P* to P if and only if . When r(·,· takes the form , the expected regret model reduces to the (transitive) Chew/MacCrimmon/Fishburn form of Table 1. This is the most general form of the model compatible with transitivity.
- 43
In this model, the indifference curves will necessarily all cross at the same point. This (unique) point will accordingly be ranked indifferent to all lotteries in the triangle.
- 44
Because r(x,y) = -r(y,x) for all x and y implies , P* will be preferred to P if and only if .
- 45
It is important to note that although the function plays a role very similar to the local utility index , it is a different concept. Unlike the linear approximation to a nonlinear preference function, the previous inequality is both exact and global.
- 46
Loomes and Sugden (1982), for example, have shown that the many of these effects follow if one assumes that r(x,y) = Q(x-y) where Q is convex for positive values and concave for negative values.
- 47
Although this point in the discussion has been reached by an examination of the preference reversal phenomenon over risky prospects, it is important to note that neither the evidence of response mode effects (e.g., Slovic, 1975) nor their implications for economic analysis are confined to the case of choice under uncertainty.
- 48
A final "twist" on the preference reversal phenomenon: Karni and Safra (1987) and Holt (1986) have shown how the procedures used in most of these studies, namely, the Becker, De-Groot, and Marschak elicitation technique (see footnote 36) and the practice of only selecting a few questions to actually play, will lead to truthful revelation of preferences only under the additional assumption that the individual satisfies the independence axiom. Accordingly, it is possible to construct (and these researchers have done so) examples of non-expected utility individuals with transitive underlying preferences and no response mode effects, whose optimal responses in such experiments consist of precisely the typical "preference reversal" responses. How (and whether) experimenters will be able to address this issue remains to be seen.
- 49
Even though all underlying probabilities were stated explicitly, Slovic found that individuals tended to overestimate the probabilities of these compound events.
- 51
See the discussion and references in Machina (1982:285-286).
- 50
Subjects were asked to choose either (A) a sure gain of $240 or (B) a 1/4:3/4 chance of $1,000 or $0, and to choose either (C) a sure loss of $750 or (D) a 3/4:1/4 chance of - $1,000 or $0. Eighty-four percent of the subjects chose A over B and 87 percent chose D over C, even though B + C dominates A + D, and choices over the combined distributions were unanimous when they were presented explicitly.
- 52
This is not to say that well-defined reference points never exist. The reference points involved in credit surcharges versus cash discounts, for example, seem unambiguous.
- 53
Fischhoff notes that "[i]f one can only infer frames from preferences after assuming the truth of the theory, one runs the risk of making the theory itself untestable" (p. 116).
- 54
A wonderful example, offered by my colleague Joel Sobel, is that of milk advertisements that make no reference either to price or to a particular dairy. What commodity could be more well-known than milk?
- 55
See, for example, Milne (1981). For an application of the theory of induced preferences to choice under uncertainty, see Machina (1984).
- 56
See also the discussions of Fellner (1961, 1963), Brewer (1963), Ellsberg (1963), Roberts (1963), Brewer and Fellner (1965), MacCrimmon (1968), Smith (1969), Sherman (1974), and Sinn (1980).
- 57
For an excellent discussion of the history, nature, and limitations of such approaches, see Arrow (1951).
- 58
For a comprehensive overview of this model and its analytics, see Karni (1985).
- 59
In generating these indifference curves from individuals' preferences over probability distributions, one implicitly assumes that their level of satisfaction from a given amount of money does not depend on the particular state of nature which that (i.e., that their preferences are state independent. Beginning with the next sentence, this assumption will no longer be required.
- 60
A final issue is the lack of a unified model that is capable of simultaneously handling all of the phenomena described in this paper: fanning out, the preference reversal phenomenon, framing effects, probability biases, and the Ellsberg paradox. After all, it is presumably the same individuals who are exhibiting each of these phenomena; should there not be a single model capable of generating them all? I doubt whether our current ability allows us to do this; I also doubt the need for a unified model as a prerequisite for further progress. The aspects of behavior considered in this paper are quite diverse, and if (like the wave-versus-particle properties of light) they cannot be currently unified, this does not mean that we cannot continue to learn by studying and modeling them separately.
- 61
The classic introductory expositions of the process of decision analysis are Raiffa (1968) and Schlaifer (1969).
- 62
See, for example, Keeney and Raiffa (1976).
- 63
See, for example, Grofman and Owen (1986).
- 64
The components of such models (e.g., the functions v(·), p(·), r(·), and g(·) in Table 1) can be assessed by procedures similar to the one described earlier for yon Neumann-Morgenstern utility functions.
- 65
The standard policy techniques of "benefit-cost analysis," "benefit-risk analysis," and so forth fall into this category.
- 66
In the nuclear power plant example the earlier section noted above, let us say that there was a probability p of an accident involving a loss of L, that some expected utility maximizer was just willing to accept an increase of ΔL1 in this potential loss in return for a reduction of Δp in its probability, and that some individual with fanning-out preferences was just willing to accept an increase of ΔL2 in return for this same reduction in p (ΔL2 could be greater or less than ΔL1). Should new technology reduce the initial loss probability by half to p/2, the extra loss the expected utility maximizer would be willing to accept for a (further) reduction of Dp would also drop by half (i.e., to ΔL1/2. The extra loss that the individual with fanning-out preferences would be willing to accept, however, would drop by less than half (i.e., to some amount greater than ΔL 2/2. In other words, as the probability of the accident drops, the individual with fanning-out preferences will exhibit a comparatively greater willingness to trade off increases in loss magnitude in exchange for further reductions in loss probability.
- 67
See Russell (in this volume).
Mark J. Machina is professor in the Department of Economics at the University of California, San Diego.
- The Expected Utility Model
- Violations Of Linearity In Tile Probabilities
- The Preference Reversal Phenomenon
- Framing Effects
- Other Issues: Is Probability Theory Relevant?
- Implications For Private And Public Decision Making
- Implications For Private-Sector Decision Analysis
- Acknowledgment
- Editors' Note
- References
- Choice Under Uncertainty: Problems Solved And Unsolved - Valuing Health Risks, C...Choice Under Uncertainty: Problems Solved And Unsolved - Valuing Health Risks, Costs, and Benefits for Environmental Decision Making
- CBSS4661.rev NICHD_XGC_tropSp1 Xenopus tropicalis cDNA clone IMAGE:8897175 3', m...CBSS4661.rev NICHD_XGC_tropSp1 Xenopus tropicalis cDNA clone IMAGE:8897175 3', mRNA sequencegi|126607144|gnl|dbEST|45116724|gb| 365.1|Nucleotide
Your browsing activity is empty.
Activity recording is turned off.
See more...